411 (Author at Cato Institute) https://www.cato.org/ en Cato Institute event, “John Roberts and Free Speech: A Report on the Roberts Court’s First Amendment Jurisprudence,” airs on C-SPAN 2 https://www.cato.org/multimedia/media-highlights-tv/cato-institute-event-john-roberts-free-speech-report-roberts-courts Tue, 13 Oct 2020 12:23:33 -0400 Cato Institute, Ilya Shapiro, Robert Corn-Revere https://www.cato.org/multimedia/media-highlights-tv/cato-institute-event-john-roberts-free-speech-report-roberts-courts John Roberts and Free Speech: A Report on the Roberts Court’s First Amendment Jurisprudence https://www.cato.org/multimedia/events/john-roberts-free-speech-report-roberts-courts-first-amendment-jurisprudence Ronald Collins, David L. Hudson Jr., Robert Corn-Revere, Lyrissa Lidsky, Ilya Shapiro <div class="mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <p>More than any other Supreme Court justice in recent history, John Roberts has played a&nbsp;defining role in shaping the contours of our free‐​speech law. He’s written more than twice as many majority opinions in this area than any of his colleagues, which gives his jurisprudence staying power. There’s a&nbsp;certain resolve, at once philosophical and tactical, at work here. In 95 percent of the free‐​expression cases decided during his 15‐​year tenure, Roberts has been in the majority. Equally revealing, Roberts has taken the lead opinion nearly 30 percent of the time. In other words, there’s something special about this genre of cases, something that speaks to who Roberts is and what he hopes the Court bearing his name might be remembered for. In <a href="https://www.scotusblog.com/2020/07/john-roberts-mr-first-amendment/" target="_blank">the first comprehensive report</a> on the Roberts Court’s free‐​speech jurisprudence, Ronald Collins and David Hudson—each of whom has published more than 10 books on free speech—examine the 56 such cases handed down by the Roberts Court from 2005 through 2020. Beyond its focus on Chief Justice Roberts, the authors’ eye‐​opening study provides a&nbsp;detailed look at the cases, the justices’ differing approaches, and lawyers who have played key roles in influencing the Court.</p> </div> Mon, 12 Oct 2020 16:11:04 -0400 Ronald Collins, David L. Hudson Jr., Robert Corn-Revere, Lyrissa Lidsky, Ilya Shapiro https://www.cato.org/multimedia/events/john-roberts-free-speech-report-roberts-courts-first-amendment-jurisprudence Robert Corn‐​Revere participates in the webinar, “Hot Topics in Free Speech and Free Press,” hosted by the ABA Section of Civil Rights and Social Justice https://www.cato.org/multimedia/media-highlights-tv/robert-corn-revere-participates-webinar-hot-topics-free-speech-free Thu, 21 May 2020 12:21:28 -0400 Robert Corn-Revere https://www.cato.org/multimedia/media-highlights-tv/robert-corn-revere-participates-webinar-hot-topics-free-speech-free Barr v. American Association of Political Consultants https://www.cato.org/publications/legal-briefs/barr-v-american-association-political-consultants Robert Corn-Revere, Ronald G. London, Ilya Shapiro, Trevor Burrus <div class="lead mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <p>Robo‐​calls are a&nbsp;growing issue of public concern, and the Telephone Consumer Protection Act (TCPA) is the federal law that regulates and penalizes their use. The law makes businesses who violate the many consumer‐​oriented provisions liable to private lawsuit. This is no idle threat, either; in the last ten years 21 TCPA cases have settled for over $10 million. It is also a&nbsp;favorite of states’ attorneys general, who earn popularity for targeting the sources of unwanted calls.</p> </div> , <div class="mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <p>The 1991 law was all‐​encompassing. Auto‐​dialers and pre‐​recorded calls were prohibited for political activists, local businesses, debt collectors, and charities alike. Unless a&nbsp;consumer has released their number willingly, they could not be called by such annoying methods. But in 2015, Congress passed a&nbsp;budget that contained an amendment exempting from the statute any calls made “solely to collect a&nbsp;debt owed to or guaranteed by the United States.”</p> <p>That exemption engendered a&nbsp;constitutional challenge from the American Association of Political Consultants (AAPC), arguing that the law had become a&nbsp;content‐​based restriction that is presumptively invalid under the First Amendment. Content‐​based restrictions are those that ban speech based on the content of the communication. Calls to collect government debt are different from other types of calls because of what is said on the call. The Fourth Circuit agreed that the restriction was content based but oddly “fixed” that problem by striking down the debt‐​collection exemption, which means the statute now bans more speech than before.</p> <p>The government petitioned the Supreme Court for review and the Court agreed to hear the case. Cato has filed an amicus brief in support of the AAPC. We argue that the exemption is a&nbsp;content‐​based restriction under any common‐​sense meaning of the term. Strict scrutiny is thus warranted partially because the exemption favors speech that benefits the government.</p> <p>Content‐​based restrictions are heavily scrutinized by courts partially because the government is not a&nbsp;neutral party, and it will often pass laws benefiting a&nbsp;certain type of speech. Generally, the only way the government can do that is by having regulations that select between different types of speech based on the content of the communication. While this may seem like a&nbsp;small fight over robo‐​calls, it’s important that the Court maintain a&nbsp;hard line on content‐​based restrictions. The government can’t play favorites when regulating speech because the government’s favorite is always the government.</p> </div> Wed, 01 Apr 2020 10:48:55 -0400 Robert Corn-Revere, Ronald G. London, Ilya Shapiro, Trevor Burrus https://www.cato.org/publications/legal-briefs/barr-v-american-association-political-consultants Robert Corn‐​Revere participates in the event,“Hot Topics in Free Speech and Free Press 2019,” hosted by the ABA Section of Civil Rights and Social Justice https://www.cato.org/multimedia/media-highlights-tv/robert-corn-revere-participates-eventhot-topics-free-speech-free Fri, 06 Dec 2019 12:35:57 -0500 Robert Corn-Revere https://www.cato.org/multimedia/media-highlights-tv/robert-corn-revere-participates-eventhot-topics-free-speech-free The Supreme Court: Past and Prologue: Welcoming Remarks, Introduction and Panel I: First Amendment Challenges https://www.cato.org/multimedia/events/supreme-court-past-prologue-welcoming-remarks-introduction-panel-i-first-amendment Roger Pilon, Ilya Shapiro, Clay Calvert, Paul Sherman, Robert Corn-Revere <p><strong>The Cato Institute's Center for Constitutional Studies Presents a Symposium through the Generosity of George M. Yeager</strong></p> <p>Cato's annual Constitution Day symposium marks the day in 1787 that the Constitutional Convention finished drafting the U.S. Constitution. We celebrate that event each year with the release of the new issue of the <a href="https://www.cato.org/pubs/scr/"><em>Cato Supreme Court Review</em></a> and with a day-long symposium featuring noted scholars discussing the recently concluded Supreme Court term and the important cases coming up. Past speakers have included Judges Alex Kozinski, Diane Sykes, and Douglas Ginsburg, Professors Richard Epstein, Michael McConnell, and Nadine Strossen, and Supreme Court litigators Paul Clement, Neal Katyal, and Walter Dellinger.</p> <table border="0" cellpadding="2" cellspacing="0" width="800"> </tr> <tr> <td valign="top" width="162"><strong>10:30&mdash;10:45AM</strong></td> <td valign="top" width="640"> <strong>WELCOMING REMARKS</strong><br /><br /><strong><a href="https://www.cato.org/people/roger-pilon">Roger Pilon</a></strong>, Vice President for Legal Affairs and Director, Center for Constitutional Studies, Cato Institute<br><br><strong>INTRODUCTION</strong><br><br><strong><a href="https://www.cato.org/people/ilya-shapiro">Ilya Shapiro</a></strong>, Senior Fellow in Constitutional Studies and Editor-in-Chief, <em>Cato Supreme Court Review</em><br><br> </td> </tr> <tr> <td valign="top" width="162"><strong>10:45&mdash;12:00PM</strong></td> <td valign="top" width="640"> <strong>PANEL I: FIRST AMENDMENT CHALLENGES</strong><br /><br /> Moderator: <strong><a href="https://www.cato.org/people/ilya-shapiro">Ilya Shapiro</a></strong>, Editor-in-Chief, <em>Cato Supreme Court Review</em><br><br> <strong>Clay Calvert</strong>, Director, Marion B. Brechner First Amendment Project, University of Florida<br> <strong>Paul M. Sherman</strong>, Senior Attorney, Institute for Justice<br> <strong>Bob Corn-Revere</strong>, Partner, Davis Wright Tremaine LLP<br><br> </td> </tr> </table> Mon, 18 Sep 2017 13:13:00 -0400 Roger Pilon, Ilya Shapiro, Clay Calvert, Paul Sherman, Robert Corn-Revere https://www.cato.org/multimedia/events/supreme-court-past-prologue-welcoming-remarks-introduction-panel-i-first-amendment Will President Trump Threaten Free Speech? https://www.cato.org/multimedia/events/will-president-trump-threaten-free-speech Flemming Rose, Robert Corn-Revere, Francis H. Buckley, John Samples <p>During the 2016 presidential election, Donald Trump promised to “open up” libel laws to make it easier to sue news organizations. He also criticized political donors for fostering corruption and misrule. Later, as president‐​elect, Trump criticized First Amendment protections accorded to flag burning. His critics say these statements indicate President Trump may seriously undermine free speech. His defenders doubt that, and note that Trump has actually fought censorship by confronting political correctness. He has also pioneered using social media to campaign and, in all likelihood, to govern. Finally, apart from his own actions, President Trump will nominate new members of the U.S. Supreme Court, the final arbiter in First Amendment cases. Will President Trump be good or bad for free speech? Please join us as three First Amendment experts assess what’s to come.</p> Fri, 03 Feb 2017 12:34:00 -0500 Flemming Rose, Robert Corn-Revere, Francis H. Buckley, John Samples https://www.cato.org/multimedia/events/will-president-trump-threaten-free-speech Robert Corn‐​Revere participates in the event “Free Speech: Still the ‘American Way’?” hosted by the Newseum https://www.cato.org/multimedia/media-highlights-tv/robert-corn-revere-participates-event-free-speech-still-american-way Tue, 01 Nov 2016 14:54:00 -0400 Robert Corn-Revere https://www.cato.org/multimedia/media-highlights-tv/robert-corn-revere-participates-event-free-speech-still-american-way Hate Speech Laws: Ratifying the Assassin’s Veto https://www.cato.org/publications/policy-analysis/hate-speech-laws-ratifying-assassins-veto Robert Corn-Revere <div class="lead mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <p>Recently criticisms of religion have been met by violence and threats of violence, the most infamous being the murder in Paris of several editors of the satirical weekly,&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>. The phenomenon of killing or threatening to kill those who insult you or your way of life has come to be known as the assassin’s veto. These events raise anew a&nbsp;basic question for liberal societies: how much expression must a&nbsp;free society tolerate?</p> </div> , <div class="mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <p>The United States Supreme Court has generally restricted government limits on speech. Some speech, however, does not receive protection, including expressions closely tied to violence. In the past, “fighting words” were judged unprotected by the First Amendment; the development of Court doctrine has largely eliminated this exception. American jurisprudence is based on the assumption that protections for freedom of expression will not long endure if they can be abandoned when the message is particularly repellant or its target especially sympathetic.</p> <p>European law also protects freedom of expression, although in a&nbsp;less robust way than does U.S. law. Article 10 of the European Convention on Human Rights subjects freedom of speech to important limitations understood generally as “hate speech.” In contrast to the United States, officials may apply criminal or civil sanctions to prohibited political advocacy.</p> <p>The United States faces a&nbsp;choice. Should it defend the right to offend, or opt instead to champion a&nbsp;right not to be offended? We have learned from hard experience in the United States that free expression cannot long survive without protecting outrageous and offensive speech.</p> </div> , <div class="mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <h2><strong>Introduction</strong></h2> <p>On the morning of January 7, 2015, Cherif and Said Kouachi, two brothers deeply offended by satirical drawings of the Muslim prophet Mohammad published in the French weekly newspaper Charlie Hebdo, exacted their own punishment for the perceived blasphemy. They forced their way into a&nbsp;staff meeting in the newspaper’s offices and massacred 12 people.<a href="#cite-1">1</a>&nbsp;It was yet another grim marker in the cross‐​cultural conflict illustrated by events such as the Ayatollah Khomeini’s 1989 fatwah against Salman Rushdie for writing The Satanic Verses, the 2004 murder of filmmaker Theo van Gogh on the streets of Amsterdam for perceived insults to Islam, and the violent reaction to the cartoons of Mohammad published in the Danish newspaper&nbsp;<em>Jyllands‐​Posten</em>&nbsp;in 2005. And this is just a&nbsp;partial list.<a href="#cite-2">2</a></p> <p>The phenomenon of killing or threatening to kill those who insult you or your way of life has come to be known as the assassin’s veto.<a href="#cite-3">3</a>&nbsp;It is a&nbsp;darker and more sinister version of “the heckler’s veto,” which the law of free expression is designed in substantial part to prevent. As Professor Timothy Garton Ash described it, “[w]here the heckler’s veto says merely ‘I will shout you down,’ the assassin’s version is ‘dare to express that and we will kill you.’”<a href="#cite-4">4</a>&nbsp;But where should the law come down on this? Should the law defend free expression at all costs no matter how inflammatory the language or who is offended? Or should the state’s coercive power silence those who trade in insult or invective?</p> <p>At the heart of this conflict lies a&nbsp;fundamental question: how much expression must a&nbsp;free society tolerate? It is tempting to describe this as a&nbsp;debate between those who believe in freedom of expression and those who do not, but that would be too simplistic. First, it is not a&nbsp;debate at all for people who truly believe that they may impose their sensibilities—often religious sensibilities—on others by employing violence or enforcing draconian laws. Debate depends on the free exchange of ideas, not coercion. Second, even for those societies that value freedom of expression and whose laws support it, none permit absolute free speech, whatever that may mean. So the question comes down to how much, and what kind of speech, may be limited for a&nbsp;governmental system to be considered one that protects freedom of expression. Put another way, should the legal system protect or punish the kind of inflammatory speech and drawings that prompted the assault on the Charlie Hebdo offices?</p> <h2><a name="sec-2" id="sec-2"></a><strong>Are We Charlie?</strong></h2> <p>The answer to this question is as complicated as the global reaction to the&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>&nbsp;killings themselves. The initial shock and outrage was met with a&nbsp;showing of seeming solidarity. Some two million people, including more than 40 world leaders, rallied in Paris in the name of world unity four days after the attack, even while, as critics noted, not all of them had stellar records on the freedom of expression. Nearly four million people across France joined in, united by the slogan “Je suis Charlie” (“I am Charlie”). Similar demonstrations were held around the world.<a href="#cite-5">5</a></p> <p>This reaction included many in the Muslim world. A&nbsp;number of governments, including those of Iran, Saudi Arabia, Jordan, Bahrain, Algeria, Morocco, and Qatar, issued statements denouncing the attack.<a href="#cite-6">6</a>&nbsp;The U.S.-based Council on American‐​Islamic Relations likewise condemned the killings and supported the right of free expression, including “speech that mocks faiths and religious figures.”<a href="#cite-7">7</a></p> <p>But any notion of a&nbsp;uniform response was soon dashed. As might be expected, some demonstrators and activists around the world cheered the tragedy. Muslims in the Philippines took to the streets to proclaim that the event should serve as a “moral lesson for the world to respect any kind of religion, especially the religion of Islam.” Freedom of expression, they said, “does not extend to insulting the noble and the greatest prophet of Allah.”<a href="#cite-8">8</a>&nbsp;Protesters in Pakistan displayed posters that read, “This is not freedom of expression, it is open aggression against Islam,” and similar rallies took place in Turkey, Chechnya, and elsewhere.<a href="#cite-9">9</a></p> <p>Such reactions were not confined to the streets. In a&nbsp;<em>USA Today</em>&nbsp;op‐​ed, British cleric Anjem Choudary wrote “Muslims do not believe in the concept of freedom of expression, as their speech and actions are determined by divine revelation and not based on people’s desires… This is because the Messenger Muhammad said, ‘Whoever insults a&nbsp;Prophet kill him.’”<a href="#cite-10">10</a>&nbsp;Similarly, Mohammed Junaid Thorne, an Australian Muslim, wrote, “If you want to enjoy ‘freedom of speech’ with no limits, expect others to exercise ‘freedom of action.’”<a href="#cite-11">11</a></p> <p>Some prominent non‐​Muslims expressed similar sentiments. The president of the U.S. Catholic League, Bill Donohue, wrote that&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>&nbsp;had “a long and disgusting record” of mocking religion and had its editor “not been so narcissistic, he may still be alive.”<a href="#cite-12">12</a>&nbsp;In a&nbsp;somewhat milder vein—or, at least, not blaming the victims quite as much—Pope Francis told reporters, “[o]ne cannot provoke, one cannot insult other people’s faith.”<a href="#cite-13">13</a>&nbsp;And even some supposedly familiar with traditional journalistic protections in the United States took a&nbsp;similar tack. DeWayne Wickham, Dean of Morgan State University School of Global Journalism, wrote of the&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>&nbsp;killings, “The once little‐​known French satirical news weekly crossed the line that separates free speech from toxic talk.”<a href="#cite-14">14</a></p> <p>The French reaction crystalized the bipolar response to&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>. While millions of citizens rallied to the defense of&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo,</em> France’s Justice Ministry sent a&nbsp;letter to prosecutors and judges urging more aggressive tactics against racist or anti‐​Semitic speech. The order did not mention Islam.<a href="#cite-15">15</a>&nbsp;In the first week after the&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>&nbsp;attack, 54 people were arrested for hate speech.<a href="#cite-16">16</a>&nbsp;One of those charged was comedian Dieudonné M’bala M’bala, who was convicted of condoning terrorism for tweeting “I feel like Charlie Coulibaly,” combining a&nbsp;reference to&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>&nbsp;and the name of the gunman who attacked a&nbsp;kosher supermarket.<a href="#cite-17">17</a></p> <p>The official response to controversial speech in France following the attacks underscores the stark differences between European law and the First Amendment to the U.S. Constitution, which provides that “Congress shall make no law … abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press … ‚” and which has been interpreted to protect even the most vile attacks based on race or religion.</p> <h2><a name="sec-3" id="sec-3"></a><strong>The American Way: Defending the Indefensible</strong></h2> <p>It is often said that the First Amendment is not an absolute, but, at the same time, a&nbsp;central tenet of the law protecting freedom of expression in the United States holds that it is a “prized American privilege to speak one’s mind, although not always with perfect good taste, on all public (issues).”<a href="#cite-18">18</a>&nbsp;This basic principle was established in a&nbsp;1949 First Amendment case,&nbsp;<em>Terminiello</em><em>&nbsp;v. City of Chicago</em>, in which the Supreme Court invalidated the breach of peace conviction of a&nbsp;firebrand Catholic priest whose speech “provoked a&nbsp;hostile mob and incited a&nbsp;friendly one, and threatened violence between the two.”<a href="#cite-19">19</a>&nbsp;The Court’s majority acknowledged the inflammatory nature of the remarks, but nevertheless voided Terminiello’s conviction, reasoning that “a function of free speech under our system of government is to invite dispute.” Such speech “may indeed best serve its high purpose when it induces a&nbsp;condition of unrest, creates dissatisfaction with conditions as they are, or even stirs people to anger.”<a href="#cite-20">20</a></p> <p>There was no question but that Terminiello’s words invited dispute and stirred people to anger. The confrontation provoked a&nbsp;near riot between what were characterized as pro‐​Fascist and pro‐​Communist mobs, and Father Terminiello’s remarks were littered with what now would be called hate speech. His ugly racial and ethnic slurs included condemnation of “atheistic, communistic Jewish or Zionist Jews,” and his speech provoked even more hate‐​filled and racist responses from the assembled crowd.<a href="#cite-21">21</a>&nbsp;The facts of the case divided the Court, prompting three strong dissenting opinions. In a&nbsp;characteristically well‐​written and carefully reasoned opinion, Justice Robert Jackson criticized the majority’s “dogma of absolute freedom for irresponsible and provocative utterance which almost completely sterilizes the power of local authorities to keep the peace as against this kind of tactics.”<a href="#cite-22">22</a></p> <p>But it was not so much the harshness of the speech as it was the incitement to immediate violence that separated the majority from the dissenters. Justice Jackson wrote that the First Amendment “is more tolerant of discussion than are most individuals or communities,” and that “[r]eligious, social and political topics that in other times or countries have not been open to lawful debate may be freely discussed here.” He observed that the law protects the “utmost freedom of utterance,” including the right to advocate fascism, communism, socialism, or capitalism, but also that individuals “may go far in expressing sentiments whether pro‐​semitic or anti‐​semitic, pro‐​negro or anti‐​negro, pro‐​Catholic or anti‐​Catholic.”<a href="#cite-23">23</a>&nbsp;For Justice Jackson, the key issue was the imminence of a&nbsp;riot, including the fact that police were being pelted with rocks, bottles, and even ice picks. He therefore drew the free‐​speech line at the prospect of mob violence because “[n]o mob has ever protected any liberty, even its own, but if not put down it always winds up in an orgy of lawlessness which respects no liberties.”<a href="#cite-24">24</a></p> <p>Different people may set the threshold differently, but the overriding presumption in American law is that the potential for violence—not the presence of hate—is what separates free from restricted speech. The Supreme Court in 1942 addressed this issue in&nbsp;<em>Chaplinsky</em><em>&nbsp;v. New Hampshire</em>, holding that the First Amendment does not protect so‐​called fighting words—epithets delivered directly to a&nbsp;person that are likely to provoke an immediate breach of the peace.<a href="#cite-25">25</a>&nbsp;It described such words as one among several classes of speech that it said “the prevention and punishment of which has never been thought to raise any Constitutional problem,” including “the lewd and obscene, the profane, the libelous, and the insulting or ‘fighting’ words.”<a href="#cite-26">26</a></p> <p>This categorical approach has established some limits on First Amendment protections, but the Supreme Court has kept the number of unprotected categories minimal, and it has narrowed their scope over time. Thus, and contrary to some common misperceptions, the list of epithets that might qualify as fighting words has been pared down almost to the vanishing point since&nbsp;<em>Chaplinsky</em>. In 1942, the Supreme Court considered it too obvious for argument that “the appellations ‘damn racketeer’ and ‘damn Fascist’ are epithets likely to provoke the average person to retaliation,” but it is difficult to imagine such a&nbsp;statement raising an eyebrow today.<a href="#cite-27">27</a>&nbsp;And the Court has since made it clear that it is not prepared to add to the categories of unprotected speech, explaining that the government does not have “freewheeling authority to declare new categories of speech outside the scope of the First Amendment.”<a href="#cite-28">28</a></p> <p>American law has maintained this focus on the probability of violence rather than the potential to cause offense even when the expression at issue includes racial provocation. The Court tightened its test for what constitutes illegal incitement in&nbsp;<em>Brandenburg v. Ohio</em>&nbsp;in the face of images of members of the Ku Klux Klan burning a&nbsp;cross as a&nbsp;sign of racial hatred. It held that to constitute incitement, the expression at issue must be intended to cause imminent lawless action&nbsp;<em>and</em>&nbsp;be likely to produce such an immediate result.<a href="#cite-29">29</a>&nbsp;Applying these principles, the Supreme Court struck down a&nbsp;St. Paul, Minnesota, ordinance that prohibited placing on public or private property “a symbol, object, appellation, characterization or graffiti including, but not limited to, a&nbsp;burning cross or Nazi swastika, which one knows or has reasonable grounds to know arouses, anger, alarm or resentment on others on the basis of race, color, creed, religion or gender.”<a href="#cite-30">30</a></p> <p>In the case of the St. Paul ordinance, the Court found that the measure was not directed at forestalling violent confrontation as much as preventing offense to particular groups, and was undermined by its content‐​based selectivity, which “creates the possibility that the city is seeking to handicap the expression of particular ideas.”<a href="#cite-31">31</a>&nbsp;It has since upheld a&nbsp;state law that prohibited cross burning when done for purposes of racial intimidation, but it also held that criminal intent could not be inferred from the symbolic act itself. Rather, the Constitution requires that the state must prove that any particular act of cross burning was done in order to intimidate.<a href="#cite-32">32</a></p> <p>The First Amendment presumes that “constitutional protection does not turn upon ‘the truth, popularity, or social utility of the ideas and beliefs which are offered.’”<a href="#cite-33">33</a>&nbsp;The Supreme Court repeatedly has emphasized that “[t]he history of the law of free expression is one of vindication in cases involving speech that many citizens find shabby, offensive, or even ugly,” and the government cannot justify regulation on the assumption that “the speech is not very important.”<a href="#cite-34">34</a>&nbsp;This is because “[t]he Constitution exists precisely so that opinions and judgments, including esthetic and moral judgments about art and literature, can be formed, tested, and expressed” without government interference.<a href="#cite-35">35</a>&nbsp;The Court has described “[t]he point of all speech protection” as being “to shield just those choices of content that in someone’s eyes are misguided, or even hurtful.”<a href="#cite-36">36</a></p> <p>Such principles are not always easy to uphold, particularly when the speech at issue is hateful. But American jurisprudence is based on the assumption that protections for freedom of expression will not long endure if they can be abandoned when the message is particularly repellant or its target especially sympathetic. Thus members of a&nbsp;neo‐​Nazi organization were permitted to march in Skokie, Illinois, in the mid‐​1970s, where over half the population at the time was Jewish and five to seven thousand residents were survivors of concentration camps.<a href="#cite-37">37</a>&nbsp;The Illinois Supreme Court recognized that the sight of swastikas and German‐​style uniforms was abhorrent to Jewish citizens and especially to the survivors of Nazi persecution, yet still held that the First Amendment would not permit restricting the demonstration. The court explained:</p> </div> , <blockquote class="blockquote"> <div> <p>[T]he popularity of views, their shocking quality, their obnoxiousness, and even their alarming impact are not enough. Otherwise, the preacher of any strange doctrine could be stopped; the anti‐​racist himself could be suppressed, if he undertakes to speak in “restricted” areas; and one who asks that public schools be open indiscriminately to all ethnic groups could be lawfully suppressed, if only he chose to speak where persuasion is needed most.&nbsp;<a href="#cite-38">38</a></p> </div> </blockquote> <cite> </cite> , <div class="mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <p>A distinctive feature of American law is that the government cannot take sides where speech is at issue. Thus, the First Amendment protects radical priests and Vatican critics alike.<a href="#cite-39">39</a>&nbsp;It also protects militant civil‐​rights activists and white supremacists equally.&nbsp;<a href="#cite-40">40</a>&nbsp;It likewise shields those who would speak for or against a&nbsp;woman’s right to terminate a&nbsp;pregnancy.<a href="#cite-41">41</a>&nbsp;And it protects those who would burn American flags or crosses as a&nbsp;form of protest, just as it does those who display them with pride.&nbsp;<a href="#cite-42">42</a>&nbsp;In short, the First Amendment requires “the government must remain neutral in the marketplace of ideas.”&nbsp;<a href="#cite-43">43</a></p> <p>It does so not because speech is impotent or lacks the capacity to cause suffering. Rather, the First Amendment is premised on the understanding that speech is powerful. “It can stir people to action, move them to tears of both joy and sorrow, and … inflict great pain.”<a href="#cite-44">44</a>&nbsp;This understanding was put to the test when the Supreme Court considered whether the Constitution protects even the speech of the Westboro Baptist Church. This peculiar family cult of religious fundamentalists believes that their god hates the United States because of the nation’s tolerance of homosexuality, among other things. And it has chosen as one principal venue for its hateful message the funerals of servicemen, where the cult displays picket signs with messages such as “Thank God for Dead Soldiers,” “Fags Doom Nations,” “God Hates Fags,” and “You’re Going to Hell.”<a href="#cite-45">45</a></p> <p>The Westboro Baptist Church’s members are careful to obey laws governing public assemblies, to keep their distance (often set by ordinance) from the actual funerals, and to obey police instructions.<a href="#cite-46">46</a>&nbsp;So when in&nbsp;<em>Snyder v. Phelps</em>&nbsp;the Supreme Court reviewed a&nbsp;decision involving a&nbsp;multimillion dollar judgment against the church for intentional infliction of emotional distress, the case focused entirely on whether the First Amendment extends to such scurrilous speech. The trial court had awarded the family of Matthew Snyder, the fallen serviceman in the case, $5 million in compensatory and punitive damages, holding that the hurtfulness and outrageousness of the speech deprived it of First Amendment protection. The United States Court of Appeals for the Fourth Circuit reversed the decision, and the Supreme Court affirmed in an 8–1 decision.</p> <p>Chief Justice Roberts’s opinion for the Court observed that the messages displayed by the Westboro Baptist Church members “may fall short of refined social or political commentary” but that the issues they raise “are matters of public import” and “certainly convey Westboro’s position on those issues.” As a&nbsp;consequence, their speech received the highest level of First Amendment protection.<a href="#cite-47">47</a>&nbsp;And that constitutional immunity was not diminished because the speech was especially outrageous. The Court observed that outrageousness was a&nbsp;highly subjective and malleable concept that could easily become a&nbsp;vehicle to suppress vehement, caustic, or unpleasant speech. It concluded that we “must tolerate insulting, and even outrageous, speech in order to provide adequate ‘breathing space’ to the freedoms protected by the First Amendment.”<a href="#cite-48">48</a></p> <h2><a name="sec-4" id="sec-4"></a><strong>The European Approach: A&nbsp;Question of Balance</strong></h2> <p>European law also protects freedom of expression, although in a&nbsp;less robust way than does U.S. law. Article 10 of the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR), based on Article 19 of the UN’s Universal Declaration of Human Rights, states that “everyone has the right to freedom of expression,” including the “freedom of hold opinions and to receive and impart information and ideas without interference by public authority and regardless of frontiers,” but that guarantee is subject to certain important limitations. First, Article 17 of the ECHR provides that no state, group, or individual has the “right to engage in any activity or perform any act aimed at the destruction of any of the rights and freedoms set forth herein.” And even though Article 10 protects free expression, it also conditions this right on restrictions deemed necessary to preserve other values, including “the protection of the reputation and rights of others.”<a href="#cite-49">49</a>&nbsp;The Council of Europe’s Additional Protocol to the Convention on Cybercrime, concerning the criminalization of acts of a&nbsp;racist and xenophobic nature committed through computer systems, likewise recognizes freedom of expression as “one of the essential foundations of a&nbsp;democratic society” and a&nbsp;basic condition “for [social] progress and for the development of every human being.” But it also requires signatories to criminalize such things as using a&nbsp;computer system to insult persons based on race, color, descent, national origin, or religion, or to deny, minimize, approve, or justify acts of genocide.<a href="#cite-50">50</a></p> <p>In short, European law protects free speech, but is subject to more of a&nbsp;multifactor balancing test. The first step in this balancing regime is to decide whether the speech at issue is free expression that is entitled to the ECHR’s protection. Under Article 17, certain expression may be excluded from the protections of the Convention—including Article 10—if the speech is determined to be hate speech, which negates the fundamental values of the ECHR. The Council of Europe has explained that Article 17 “aims at guaranteeing the preservation of the system of democratic values underpinning the convention notably by preventing totalitarian groups from exercising the rights set by the convention in a&nbsp;way to destroy the rights and liberties established by the convention itself.”<a href="#cite-51">51</a></p> <p>The European Court of Human Rights has ruled that “there is no doubt that any remark directed against the Convention’s underlying values would be removed from the protection of Article 10 by Article 17.”&nbsp;<a href="#cite-52">52</a>&nbsp;Under this process of exclusion, the court has held that anti‐​Semitic speech,<a href="#cite-53">53</a>political advocacy based on racial divisiveness,<a href="#cite-54">54</a>&nbsp;and Holocaust denial,<a href="#cite-55">55</a>&nbsp;among other things, are outside the protection of Article 10. Religious intolerance is also excluded from Article 10 protection. In one notable case a&nbsp;person was convicted of aggravated hostility toward a&nbsp;religious group for displaying a&nbsp;poster supplied by the British National Party that depicted a&nbsp;World Trade Center in flames with the caption “Islam out of Britain—Protect the British People.” The European Court of Human Rights denied Article 10 protection, finding that a&nbsp;general, vehement attack on a&nbsp;religious group, linking it with a&nbsp;grave act of terrorism, constituted an act within the meaning of Article 17 because it was incompatible with the values proclaimed by the Convention.<a href="#cite-56">56</a></p> <p>Assuming speech clears the Article 17 hurdle, it is then subject to the balancing process set forth in Article 10. Under Article 10, freedom of expression may be conditioned or restricted as prescribed by particular national laws when such limits “are necessary in a&nbsp;democratic society, in the interests of national security, territorial integrity or public safety, for the prevention of disorder or crime, for the protection of health or morals, for the protection of the reputation or rights of others, for preventing the disclosure of information received in confidence, or for maintaining the authority and impartiality of the judiciary.”<a href="#cite-57">57</a>&nbsp;In applying Article 10, the European Court of Human Rights examines whether a&nbsp;member state’s limitation on freedom of expression satisfies various requirements, beginning with determining whether the restriction was authorized by the applicable national law.</p> <p>In this regard, European countries historically have restricted hate speech through both criminal and civil law, and, pursuant to European Directive, all EU member states must criminalize “serious manifestations of racism and xenophobia” and to make such expression punishable by “effective, proportionate and dissuasive penalties.”<a href="#cite-58">58</a>&nbsp;In France, for example, the Press Law of 1881 prohibits incitement to racial discrimination, hatred, or violence on the basis of national origin or membership in an ethnic, national, racial, or religious group.<a href="#cite-59">59</a>&nbsp;Article 266(b) of the Danish Criminal Code outlaws “expressing and spreading national hatred” which may include the use of threatening, vilifying, or insulting language intended for the general public.<a href="#cite-60">60</a>&nbsp;In the Netherlands, Articles 137(c) and (d) of the Criminal Code prohibit engaging in verbal, written, or illustrated incitement to hatred on account of race, religion, sexual orientation, or personal convictions.<a href="#cite-61">61</a>&nbsp;And in the United Kingdom, the Public Order Act of 1986 provides that “a person who uses threatening, abusive, or insulting words or behaviour, or displays any written material which is threatening, abusive, or insulting” may be penalized if he “intends to stir up racial hatred” or if “having regard to all the circumstances racial hatred is likely to be stirred up thereby.”<a href="#cite-62">62</a></p> <p>Assuming a&nbsp;given restriction on speech was authorized by national law, review under Article 10 asks whether the restriction falls within the legitimate aims of the Convention and whether limiting speech is necessary in a&nbsp;democratic society to achieve one or more of the objectives set forth in the Article. The European Court of Human Rights has ruled that restrictions on speech are necessary only if they respond to a&nbsp;pressing social need, but that national authorities are provided a&nbsp;margin of appreciation, or, rather, a&nbsp;high degree of latitude, in such determinations. In a&nbsp;given case, the court will take into account various factors, including the objective of the speaker; the content of the speech; its context (e.g., whether the speaker is a&nbsp;politician or a&nbsp;journalist); the profile of the person or group who were the targets of the speech; and the potential impact of the speech, including whether it was widely disseminated. Against these factors, the court will weigh the gravity of the speech restriction to determine whether the means employed are proportionate to the social values to be served.&nbsp;<a href="#cite-63">63</a></p> <p>With this many variables it can be quite difficult to discern when speech crosses the line from acceptable discourse to illegal hate speech. The Council of Europe has acknowledged that there is no universally agreed definition, but points to a&nbsp;1997 recommendation by its Committee of Ministers that defines hate speech as including “all forms of expression which spread, incite, promote or justify racial hatred, xenophobia, anti‐​Semitism or other forms of hatred based on intolerance, including: intolerance expressed by aggressive nationalism and ethnocentrism, discrimination and hostility against minorities, migrants and people of immigrant origin.”<a href="#cite-64">64</a>&nbsp;Defining this rather broad class of expression is further complicated by the Council’s acknowledgment that “[t]he identification of expressions that could be qualified as ‘hate speech’ is sometimes difficult because this kind of speech does not necessarily manifest itself through the expression of hatred or of emotions. It can also be concealed in statements which at a&nbsp;first glance may seem to be rational or normal.”<a href="#cite-65">65</a></p> <p>Under this framework it is not uncommon for political advocacy to be subjected to criminal or civil sanctions. In 2009, Daniel Féret, a&nbsp;member of Belgium’s parliament and chairman of the political party Front National (FN), was convicted of incitement to racial discrimination and sentenced to community service and disqualified from holding parliamentary office for 10&nbsp;years. The conviction was for distributing leaflets with such slogans as “Stand up against the Islamification of Belgium,” “Stop the Sham Integration Policy,” and “Send non‐​European job‐​seekers home.” The European Court of Human Rights held that the conviction did not violate Article 10 because the campaign literature “sought to make fun of the immigrants concerned,” with the inevitable risk of arousing feelings of distrust, rejection, or even hatred towards foreigners, “particularly among less knowledgeable members of the public.”<a href="#cite-66">66</a>&nbsp;The court reached a&nbsp;similar decision in 2010&nbsp;in the case of Jean‐​Marie Le Pen, then chairman of the French National Front party, for saying in a&nbsp;newspaper interview that “the day there are no longer 5&nbsp;million but 25 million Muslims in France, they will be in charge.” It found that the interference with the applicant’s enjoyment of his right to freedom of expression had been “necessary in a&nbsp;democratic society.”<a href="#cite-67">67</a></p> <h2><a name="sec-5" id="sec-5"></a><strong>How Do the Systems Compare?</strong></h2> <p>Both the United States and the EU nations consider freedom of expression to be a&nbsp;fundamental right, and in neither system is free speech treated as an absolute. Yet free speech cases in the respective legal systems yield very different results. The United States protects speech that would never be tolerated under European law, and European nations impose both criminal and civil penalties for expression to a&nbsp;degree that is unthinkable in the United States. What are the principal reasons for these differences?</p> <p>European countries have taken the opposite approach. Various countries have long prohibited hate speech (among many other classes of speech that would be protected in the United States), and the European Convention on Human Rights reinforces that tradition. Notwithstanding the Article 10 guarantee that “everyone has the right to freedom of expression,” speech may be excluded from the protections of the ECHR under Article 17 if it is considered to be an abuse of free expression because it is incompatible with the values proclaimed by the Convention.<a href="#cite-70">70</a>&nbsp;What may be considered incompatible is not bound by any fixed categories and is subject to expansion.</p> <p>No such concept as strict scrutiny exists under the ECHR. Instead, the European Court of Human Rights weighs the various factors—including the objective of the speaker, the content of the speech and its context, the profile of the targets of the speech, and the impact—against the gravity of the speech restrictions. If the perceived social value of the expression is sufficient, or if the restrictions are considered severe, then Article 10 may provide protection—or it may not. The court is also required to consider the relative social importance of the speech and the prominence of the speaker.<a href="#cite-75">75</a></p> <p>The European court has said that freedom of expression extends not just to ideas that are “favourably received or regarded as inoffensive” but also to those that “offend, shock or disturb the state or any sector of the population.” It has also said that religious groups “must tolerate and accept the denial by others of their religious beliefs and even the propagation by others of doctrines hostile to their faith.”<a href="#cite-79">79</a>&nbsp;But it is difficult to expect such protections to be firm or predictable where member states are accorded a&nbsp;margin of appreciation in applying their hate‐​speech laws, and where the court decisions suggest that “[t]he identification of ‘hate speech’ is sometimes difficult because this kind of speech does not necessarily manifest itself through the expression of hatred or emotions.” Such speech “can be concealed in statements which at first glance may seem to be rational or normal.”<a href="#cite-80">80</a>&nbsp;Given the number of factors the court is called upon to balance, it is hard to predict whether the tie goes to the speaker or to the censor. The only honest answer can be “it depends.”</p> <ol type="1"><li> <p><strong>Limited vs. Open‐​Ended Exceptions.</strong>&nbsp;Under the First Amendment to the U.S. Constitution, protection for free speech is the default position and exceptions are few and narrowly defined. In fact, after the Supreme Court in&nbsp;<em>Chaplinsky</em>&nbsp;enumerated classes of speech that “the prevention and punishment of which has never been thought to raise any Constitutional problem,” the list of unprotected categories has been reduced and the scope of the remaining classes more focused.<a href="#cite-68">68</a>&nbsp;While the First Amendment exceptions still include incitement to violence and true threats, they do not cover insults based on race or religion. The Supreme Court has more recently rejected the concept of “freewheeling authority to declare new categories of speech outside the scope of the First Amendment.”<a href="#cite-69">69</a></p> </li> <li> <p><strong>Strict Scrutiny</strong><strong>v</strong><strong>ersus</strong><strong>Proportionality.</strong>&nbsp;When the government seeks to restrict the content of speech in the United States it is subject to strict scrutiny. Under this level of review, the government has the burden to prove a&nbsp;restriction on speech is necessary to serve a&nbsp;compelling interest and that it has employed the least restrictive means of achieving its purpose.<a href="#cite-71">71</a>&nbsp;For that reason, it is the rare case where a&nbsp;content‐​based restriction can survive such scrutiny.<a href="#cite-72">72</a>&nbsp;Moreover, the government lacks the ability to regulate speech based on its purported value. Outside the limited (and anomalous) area of obscenity, where courts ask whether patently offensive, graphic sexual material lacks serious literary, artistic, political or scientific value,<a href="#cite-73">73</a>&nbsp;the Supreme Court has made clear that serious value cannot be used “as a&nbsp;general precondition to protecting&nbsp;<em>other</em>&nbsp;types of speech in the first place.” After all, the Court reasoned, “‘[<em>m</em>]<em>ost</em>&nbsp;of what we say to one another lacks “religious, political, scientific, educational, journalistic, historical, or artistic value’ (let alone serious value), but it is sheltered from government regulation.”<a href="#cite-74">74</a></p> </li> <li> <p><strong>Benefit of the Doubt for Speech.</strong>&nbsp;In the United States, the presumption favors freedom of expression, and the speaker gets the benefit of the doubt. This concept has been expressed in various ways, most often with the dictum that First Amendment freedoms need “breathing space” to survive.<a href="#cite-76">76</a>&nbsp;Or, as Chief Justice Roberts has written, “[w]here the First Amendment is implicated, the tie goes to the speaker, not the censor.”<a href="#cite-77">77</a>&nbsp;But the balancing calculus used by the European Court of Human Rights gives breathing space to the national laws that regulate speech. Applying Article 10, the court seeks to determine whether there is a&nbsp;pressing social need to restrict freedom of expression and whether the means used are proportionate to the government’s legitimate aim. In this analysis, national authorities are accorded a&nbsp;certain margin of appreciation in how they enforce their laws.<a href="#cite-78">78</a>&nbsp;In short, it is the state—not the speaker—that enjoys the benefit of the doubt.</p> </li> <li> <p><strong>Treatment of Intermediaries.</strong>&nbsp;Under U.S. law, those who provide online platforms for third‐​party speech receive broad immunity from liability. Section 230 of the Communications Decency Act provides, among other things, that online services cannot be treated “as the publisher or speaker of any information provided by another information content provider.”<a href="#cite-81">81</a>&nbsp;Congress adopted this provision in support of First Amendment values “to maintain the robust nature of Internet communication and, accordingly, to keep government interference in the medium to a&nbsp;minimum.”<a href="#cite-82">82</a>&nbsp;And it has had its intended effect. Freedom of expression has flourished online, but with it—inevitably—comes hateful speech. As a&nbsp;consequence, a&nbsp;recent decision of the European Court of Human Rights held that the publisher of a&nbsp;commercially run news portal could be held responsible for comments posted by third parties. In&nbsp;<em>Delfi</em><em>&nbsp;AS v. Estonia</em>, the court found no violation of Article 10 after the news site was fined for failing to take down anti‐​Semitic readers’ comments. It decided the finding of liability had been justified and was a&nbsp;proportionate restriction on the portal’s freedom of expression.<a href="#cite-83">83</a>&nbsp;Thus far, the holding applies to commercially run news sites that allow readers to post comments, but not to general social media platforms. The holding in&nbsp;<em>Delfi</em><em>&nbsp;AS</em>&nbsp;was moderated somewhat in a&nbsp;subsequent decision, which held that it would violate Article 10 to impose civil liability on website operators for third‐​party content. But the case presented a&nbsp;different issue, for the comments did not include hate speech. The court also held that it would be sufficient for the websites to maintain an effective “notice and takedown” regime, something that would be considered a&nbsp;heckler’s veto under U.S. law.<a href="#cite-84">84</a></p> </li> </ol><h2><a name="sec-6" id="sec-6"></a><strong>A Grave Test</strong></h2> <p>Tragedies such as the&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>&nbsp;massacre raise important questions about these different approaches to freedom of expression. Some have asked whether U.S. law should even allow the kind of inflammatory speech that is the hallmark of&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>. But if such restrictions are to be imposed, would it not ratify and give official sanction to the assassin’s veto? And if the potential to offend is sufficient to justify censorship, whose sensibilities should define the limits of free expression? Is the agenda to be set by those willing to commit violence in response to images that upset them or transgress their religion? If that is the case, is the&nbsp;<em>Book of Mormon</em>&nbsp;musical, with its profanity and sacrilegious content, permissible only because the Church of Jesus Christ of the Latter Day Saints is unlikely to declare a&nbsp;jihad? Or should the law restrict expression to buffer <em>everyone’s</em>&nbsp;perceived sensibilities? Under that approach, the question is no longer what speech crosses the line to be an abuse of free speech; it is what speech does not?</p> <p>These questions are far from academic. A&nbsp;little more than a&nbsp;month after the&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>&nbsp;attack, a&nbsp;lone‐​wolf gunman in Copenhagen attacked a&nbsp;café that hosted a&nbsp;debate on freedom of speech entitled “Art, Blasphemy and the Freedom of Expression.” The event was organized by artist Lars Vilks, who had drawn one of the Mohammad cartoons published in&nbsp;<em>Jyllands‐​Posten</em>&nbsp;in 2005. Vilks survived the attack, but Danish documentary filmmaker Finn Nørgaard was killed.&nbsp;<a href="#cite-85">85</a>&nbsp;None of the panelists at the free‐​speech event had anything to do with the Mohammad cartoons, thus expanding the assassin’s veto beyond those who insult the Prophet to speakers who merely talk about whether insulting the Prophet should be permitted. For radical religious fundamentalists, there is no room for debate.</p> <p>In May, two gunmen were killed by police in Garland, Texas, after they opened fire on a “Draw Mohammad Contest” sponsored by the American Freedom Defense Initiative.<a href="#cite-86">86</a>&nbsp;The event, conceived by controversial blogger Pamela Geller as a&nbsp;response to the&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>&nbsp;attack, was roundly criticized as being needlessly and intentionally provocative.<a href="#cite-87">87</a>&nbsp;Bill O’Reilly of Fox News argued it was wrong “to insult every Muslim on the planet” and he surmised that “Jesus would not have sponsored that event.”<a href="#cite-88">88</a>&nbsp;Representative Peter King said that the contest “went too far,” was insulting to Muslims, and “put people’s lives at risk needlessly.”&nbsp;<a href="#cite-89">89</a>&nbsp;And CNN news commentator Chris Cuomo took the position that the event was hate speech and therefore not protected under the First Amendment, even citing&nbsp;<em>Chaplinsky</em>&nbsp;for that proposition.<a href="#cite-90">90</a></p> <p>Cuomo was dead wrong about the law, but his reaction, and those of others, illustrates that many people believe the United States should adopt a&nbsp;more European approach to freedom of expression. One of the more prominent voices was that of cartoonist Garry Trudeau, who called what&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>&nbsp;did with its Mohammad cartoons “an abuse of satire.” In remarks made as he accepted the George Polk Career Award for journalism in April 2015, the&nbsp;<em>Doonesbury</em>&nbsp;creator criticized&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>&nbsp;and&nbsp;<em>Jyllands‐​Posten</em>&nbsp;for publishing cartoons of Mohammad and slammed “free speech absolutists” for defending them. He compared the cartoons to crude and vulgar graffiti that “punches down” and attacks the little guy, thereby wandering “into the realm of hate speech.”<a href="#cite-91">91</a>&nbsp;Later that same month 145 writers signed a&nbsp;letter protesting the PEN American Center’s decision to present its annual Freedom of Expression Courage award to&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>, and six writers backed out as literary hosts for the award dinner.<a href="#cite-92">92</a>&nbsp;Academic writers have also suggested that the American system goes too far in protecting free speech.<a href="#cite-93">93</a></p> <p>It is unlikely such criticism will lead to changes in American law, although recent cases and legislation have had the effect of limiting the display of symbols characterized as hate speech. In 2015 the Supreme Court decided that it did not violate the First Amendment for Texas to reject a&nbsp;depiction of the Confederate battle flag as part of its specialty license plate program on grounds it was considered offensive. The issue in that case was not whether the state could ban images of the flag, but whether the specialty plate program constituted government speech, which is not covered by First Amendment constraints. A&nbsp;divided Court held that license plates are government property and that they convey government speech notwithstanding the messages permitted as part of the specialty plate program.<a href="#cite-94">94</a>&nbsp;Similarly, South Carolina decided to remove the Confederate flag from its State Capitol grounds in the wake of the racially motivated murder of nine churchgoers in Charleston.&nbsp;<a href="#cite-95">95</a>&nbsp;Both examples involved government sponsorship of offensive speech, not whether an individual could be punished for displaying the flag.</p> <p>But while a&nbsp;change in American constitutional law is unlikely in this regard, there has been movement by some on the Supreme Court. In a&nbsp;series of recent opinions, Justice Stephen Breyer has articulated a&nbsp;theory of proportionality in First Amendment cases that sounds distinctly European. In<em>United States v. Alvarez</em>, in which the Court invalidated the “Stolen Valor Act,” Justice Breyer concurred, but said he would not apply strict scrutiny to reach that result. Rather, he wrote that the Court should employ a&nbsp;form of intermediate scrutiny that asks “whether the statute works speech‐​related harm that is out of proportion to its justifications.”<a href="#cite-96">96</a></p> <p>He has floated the same theory in other cases as well. Dissenting from a&nbsp;2011 decision that invalidated a&nbsp;California law regulating violence‐​themed video games, Justice Breyer opined that the Court should not have applied strict scrutiny but should have asked whether, overall, “the statute works speech‐​related harm … out of proportion to the benefits that the statute seeks to provide.”<a href="#cite-97">97</a>&nbsp;And in another dissent, this time from a&nbsp;decision striking down a&nbsp;commercial speech regulation, Justice Breyer again wrote, “I would ask whether Vermont’s regulatory provisions work harm to First Amendment interests that is disproportionate to their furtherance of legitimate regulatory objectives.”<a href="#cite-98">98</a>&nbsp;In this dissent he was joined by Justices Ruth Bader Ginsburg and Elena Kagan.</p> <p>Justice Breyer suggested how this theory of proportionality would apply in a&nbsp;case involving hate speech in his concurring opinion in&nbsp;<em>Snyder v. Phelps</em>, the case involving funeral protests by the Westboro Baptist Church. While Justice Breyer agreed with the majority that the church could not be penalized for its offensive speech on the facts of the case, he wrote that “[t]o uphold the application of state law in these circumstances would punish Westboro for seeking to communicate its views on matters of public concern without proportionately advancing the State’s interest in protecting its citizens against severe emotional harm.”<a href="#cite-99">99</a>&nbsp;The implication of his opinion is that he would have voted to uphold the jury verdict against the church if he had found it to be proportionate.</p> <p>If this sounds like the way the European Court of Human Rights operates, it is because it is. In exercising its powers of review over member states’ restrictions on speech (including hate speech), the ECHR “assesses the proportionality of a&nbsp;restriction on freedom of expression to the aim pursued.” Any interference “disproportionate to the legitimate aim pursued will not be deemed ‘necessary in a&nbsp;democratic society’ and will thus contravene Article 10 of the Convention.”<a href="#cite-100">100</a>&nbsp;Assessment of the proportionality of the response varies from case to case, depending on the court’s estimation of the magnitude of the government’s interest and the importance of the rights in question.</p> <p>Justice Breyer acknowledged his intellectual debt to these sources in his 2015 book&nbsp;<em>The Court and the World.</em> He wrote that he has found the legal concept of proportionality “often used by European and other foreign judges” to be “useful in describing and applying classical American rules of constitutional law.”<a href="#cite-101">101</a>&nbsp;He does not suggest elimination of traditional modes of First Amendment analysis—such as strict scrutiny—but argues “they are not, and cannot be, the whole story where the First Amendment is concerned.” Justice Breyer advocates supplementing traditional levels of First Amendment scrutiny with a&nbsp;form of balancing—“[a]nd that is where proportionality comes in.”<a href="#cite-102">102</a>&nbsp;Specifically, he favors “adding the judge‐​made concept of proportionality as a&nbsp;guide in deciding First Amendment cases.”&nbsp;<a href="#cite-103">103</a></p> <p>Reviewing his dissenting opinion in&nbsp;<em>Sorrell</em>&nbsp;as well as some of his concurrences (which read remarkably like his dissents), Justice Breyer noted that “my view of the case would likely have prevailed” if the Court adopted a&nbsp;more European balancing approach. He argues that proportionality better enables judges to analyze how statutes actually operate and would “produce results more consistent with the First Amendment’s purposes.”<a href="#cite-104">104</a>&nbsp;Of course, that necessarily would mean revising current law to be more in line with Justice Breyer’s view of the First Amendment’s purpose, which would require reversing a&nbsp;number of recent decisions upholding free expression claims, such as&nbsp;<em>Brown v. EMA</em>, in which the Court’s majority invalidated California’s regulation of violence‐​themed video games. It also would mean adopting a&nbsp;more European approach toward so‐​called hate speech.</p> <h2><a name="sec-7" id="sec-7"></a><strong>Where does this leave&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>?</strong></h2> <p>United States constitutional law forcefully repudiates the assassin’s veto, and publications such as&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>&nbsp;unquestionably receive the law’s full protection in this country. So do the anti‐​Semitic routines of Dieudonné. This is because formative First Amendment decisions were predicated on vanquishing the assassin’s veto’s weaker cousin, the heckler’s veto. The Supreme Court repeatedly reaffirmed its holding from&nbsp;<em>Terminiello</em>&nbsp;that threats of violence from “angry and turbulent” hostile audiences cannot justify censorship, most notably in cases arising from the civil rights movement where the danger of a&nbsp;violent crowd reaction was commonplace.</p> <p>Limiting civil rights speakers because of the fear that angry mobs might shatter domestic tranquility would have severely undermined both the First Amendment and the cause of equality.<a href="#cite-105">105</a>&nbsp;As a&nbsp;consequence, the Supreme Court held that controversial speakers cannot be punished or silenced simply because “their critics might react with disorder or violence.”<a href="#cite-106">106</a>&nbsp;And, based on the principle of content neutrality, the same principles extend to speakers who are hostile to the cause of civil rights<a href="#cite-107">107</a>&nbsp;and to those who raise controversial issues as well.<a href="#cite-108">108</a>&nbsp;Accordingly, the Court held that the act of burning an American flag as a&nbsp;form of protest is protected by the First Amendment despite the possibility that offended onlookers might react with violence.<a href="#cite-109">109</a></p> <p>American hostility to the heckler’s veto was most forcefully reaffirmed by the&nbsp;<em>en</em> <em>banc</em>&nbsp;Sixth Circuit in a&nbsp;case with particular relevance to the&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>&nbsp;controversy. In&nbsp;<em>Bible Believers v. Wayne County, Michigan</em>, the court held that police violated the First Amendment rights of members an evangelical Christian group for ejecting them from an Arab culture festival because of their intentionally provocative speech. The evangelicals attended the festival to proselytize, and their essential message was one of intolerance—“proclaiming that Mohammed was a&nbsp;false prophet who lied to them and that Muslims would be damned to hell if they failed to repent by rejecting Islam.”<a href="#cite-110">110</a>&nbsp;Their message was calculated to be inflammatory, including signs reading “Islam is a&nbsp;Religion of Blood and Murder,” “Turn or Burn,” and “Your Prophet Is a&nbsp;Pedophile.” And if that were not enough, the Bible Believers carried a&nbsp;severed pig’s head on a&nbsp;spike to, as they explained it, “ke[ep] [the Muslims] at bay.”<a href="#cite-111">111</a>&nbsp;Not surprisingly, they provoked a&nbsp;number of angry reactions, including profane taunts and being pelted with plastic bottles and other debris.</p> <p>The Sixth Circuit held in a&nbsp;divided opinion that threatening the Bible Believers with arrest if they failed to leave the festival in response to the hostile crowd reaction was a&nbsp;classic heckler’s veto. The majority concluded that the offensive religious message delivered in a&nbsp;public forum did not fit into a&nbsp;recognized First Amendment exception such as incitement or fighting words, and that the police had an obligation to protect the speakers rather than “join a&nbsp;roiling mob intent on suppressing ideas.”<a href="#cite-112">112</a>&nbsp;Although the Bible Believers’ message was “vile and offensive to most every person who believes in the right of their fellow citizens to practice the faith of his or her choosing,” the court found that “freedom to espouse sincerely held religious, political, or philosophical beliefs, especially in the face of hostile opposition, is too important to our democratic institution for it to be abridged simply due to the hostility of reactionary listeners who may be offended by a&nbsp;speaker’s message.”<a href="#cite-113">113</a>&nbsp;It reaffirmed the principle that “the answer to disagreeable speech is not violent retaliation by offended listeners or ratification of the heckler’s veto through threat of arrest by the police.”<a href="#cite-114">114</a></p> <p>Critics say that U.S. law goes too far in an absolutist direction in that it protects speech that is hateful, hurtful, or that may foment social unrest. And while they don’t condone the murderous reactions to the likes of&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo’s</em>&nbsp;slashing satire, they get the motivations underlying the violent backlash. Critics from across the political spectrum argue that this takes free speech too far, and that such expression should be silenced. Hate‐​speech laws operate on the same principle, imposing limits on freedom of expression in the name of civility and social order. They substitute state power in the form of criminal penalties or civil sanctions for extremist vigilante actions, but they begin with the same premise—freedom of speech does not include the right to say [insert your preferred epithet or satirical cartoon here].</p> <p>European law assumes that these vital interests can be balanced under a&nbsp;rule of law. Freedom of expression can be protected to a&nbsp;significant degree, but these protections give way when necessary to preserve countervailing values of democracy and equality. This not an easy balancing act to perform, and it may not always be so clear that the law is what rules, as opposed to the judges’ personal preferences. In a&nbsp;2015 address at Catholic University School of Law, Wolfgang Brandstetter, the Austrian federal minister of justice, explained that Austrian law prohibits hate speech and hate crimes, imposing jail terms of up to two years for a&nbsp;violation. “For us, hate speech is misusing freedom of speech, and therefore shouldn’t be permitted,” he said, but he acknowledged the difficulty of maintaining consistency. He noted that denying or trivializing the genocidal crimes of Adolf Hitler could be prosecuted under hate‐​speech laws, but denying those of Joseph Stalin would not. He added that “speech involving religion causes the worst problems of all.”<a href="#cite-115">115</a></p> <p>Religion necessarily raises the thorniest problems, as it is difficult to explain how to prohibit insults to religion as a&nbsp;form of hate speech without effectively criminalizing blasphemy. And it is not just a&nbsp;matter of prohibiting blasphemy against an official religion, but against&nbsp;<em>all</em>&nbsp;religions. This is especially true when satire is involved, as illustrated by the reaction to&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>. Some, such as the Pope, Garry Trudeau, or Bill O’Reilly, will condemn you for it; others, such as Cherif and Said Kouachi, will kill you because of it; while some governments will merely ban your work or jail you for it.</p> <p>For example, Polish authorities imposed a&nbsp;fine of 1,200 euros on Doda, a&nbsp;popular rock performer, for her statements that the Bible was written by people “drunk with wine and smoking some stuff” and that she “believes more in dinosaurs than the Bible.” She was charged under Article 196 of the Polish Criminal Code, which prohibits offending “religious feelings of other people by publicly insulting an object of religious cult or a&nbsp;place for holding of religious ceremonies.” The fine and the blasphemy law were upheld by the Polish Constitutional Court in October 2015. The court held that the right to free expression did not include a&nbsp;right to make insulting statements that offend the feelings of others, and it found the fine to be “proportionate.”<a href="#cite-116">116</a>&nbsp;Separately, a&nbsp;performer in a&nbsp;death metal band was charged for calling the Catholic Church “the most murderous cult on the planet.”<a href="#cite-117">117</a>&nbsp;In Turkey, the owner of a&nbsp;publishing company was convicted of insulting “God, the Religion, the Prophet and the Holy Book” for publishing a&nbsp;novel that addressed theological and philosophical issues. He was fined and sentenced to two years in prison, but the prison sentence was commuted.</p> <p>In the Turkish case, the European Court of Human Rights found in 2005 that Muslims could legitimately feel that certain passages of the book constituted an unwarranted and offensive attack on them, and the conviction did not violate Article 10. It noted that the authorities had not seized the book, and that the fine was proportionate to the aims of the law.<a href="#cite-118">118</a>&nbsp;Under this legal framework, could a&nbsp;film like Monty Python’s&nbsp;<em>Life of Brian</em>&nbsp;be made today? Considered a&nbsp;comedy classic, the film caused outrage at the time and was banned as sacrilegious in Ireland and Norway. (<em>Life of Brian</em>was marketed in Sweden with posters exclaiming “So funny, it was banned in Norway!”). In the UK, 39 local authorities effectively prohibited its exhibition.<a href="#cite-119">119</a></p> <p>When it comes to freedom of expression, how can one tell the difference between countries whose citizens are protected by the ECHR and those whose citizens are not?<a href="#cite-120">120</a>&nbsp;It’s not always easy to say. Three members of Pussy Riot, the punk rock protest group that performed its “Punk Prayer” in Moscow’s Christ the Savior cathedral in 2012, were convicted and each sentenced to two years for “hooliganism motivated by religious hatred.”<a href="#cite-121">121</a>&nbsp;Witnesses at the trial testified about how their religious sensibilities had been seared by the performance (“they basically spat in my face, in my soul, in my Lord’s soul,” according to one), and a&nbsp;poll found that 42 percent of Russians considered the performance “an attack on the Russian Orthodox Church.” Yet the lyrics of their song (“Virgin birth‐​giver of God, drive away Putin!”) are unmistakably a&nbsp;critique of the political order, not an attack on religion.<a href="#cite-122">122</a>&nbsp;This is not an uncommon outcome for so‐​called hate‐​speech laws. They may be interpreted too broadly or purposely used by authorities to silence dissent. After Russia adopted a&nbsp;law prohibiting Nazi propaganda, one of the first books removed from bookstores was&nbsp;<em>Maus</em>, Art Spiegelman’s Pulitzer‐​Prize‐​winning graphic novel about life in Nazi Germany—hardly a&nbsp;promotion of Nazism, but in fact, exactly the opposite.<a href="#cite-123">123</a></p> <p>Is this a&nbsp;fair comparison? After all, it might be argued that neither&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>&nbsp;nor other publications were prosecuted in Europe for printing cartoons depicting Mohammad. This is largely true, but only to a&nbsp;point. In the face of demands that&nbsp;<em>Jyllands‐​Posten</em>&nbsp;be prosecuted for its 2005 publication of Mohammad cartoons, Danish authorities declined to initiate a&nbsp;criminal case because the cartoons were published in the context of an important political debate. The decision prompted the Organization of the Islamic Conference (OIC) to demand that the European Parliament pass a&nbsp;law prohibiting Islamophobia and that the EU should impose new limits on freedom of expression regarding the use of religious symbols.<a href="#cite-124">124</a>&nbsp;The organization also has spearheaded efforts to get the United Nations to adopt resolutions prohibiting defamation of religion, a&nbsp;measure that has been likened to an international blasphemy law.</p> <p>The European response to such demands was less than firm in supporting freedom of expression. The EU’s foreign policy coordinator, Javier Solana, responded that Europeans viewed the&nbsp;<em>Jyllands‐​Posten</em>&nbsp;publication with resentment and disgust and pledged that the EU would “do its utmost to make sure that that kind of cartoon wouldn’t be published in the future.”<a href="#cite-125">125</a>&nbsp;Former Danish foreign minister Uffe Elleman‐​Jensen also condemned&nbsp;<em>Jyllands‐​Posten</em>, and said that publication of the cartoons was at odds with founding principles of democracy.<a href="#cite-126">126</a>&nbsp;More recently, British Labor Leader Ed Miliband has proposed outlawing language deemed offensive to Muslims, pledging to make Islamophobia “an aggravated crime.”<a href="#cite-127">127</a>&nbsp;Miliband, as British Foreign Secretary in 2009, had defended the decision to exclude Dutch parliamentarian Geert Wilders from entering the UK to exhibit a&nbsp;film critical of Islam. Miliband said that Britons have a “profound commitment to freedom of speech,” but “there is no freedom to stir up hate, religious and racial hatred, according to the laws of the land.”<a href="#cite-128">128</a></p> <p><em>Charlie Hebdo</em>&nbsp;republished three of the&nbsp;<em>Jyllands‐​Posten</em>&nbsp;Mohammad cartoons in 2006&nbsp;in an article discussing the growing controversy over freedom of expression, and was sued by the Paris Grand Mosque and the Union of French Islamic Organizations under French law. The Paris court held that&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>&nbsp;had not violated the law because two of the cartoons targeted radical Islamists but not Muslims in general. The third, while insulting to Muslims generally, was not published with an intent to insult, but was part of the ongoing debate about&nbsp;<em>Jyllands‐​Posten</em>&nbsp;and censorship.<a href="#cite-129">129</a>The decision was upheld on appeal.</p> <p>That case, like the decision by Danish officials not to prosecute&nbsp;<em>Jyllands‐​Posten</em>, is a&nbsp;good example of how the balancing approach in the EU can come down on the side of free expression. But the subjectivity of the reasoning suggests that neither&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>&nbsp;nor other publications may take a&nbsp;favorable outcome for granted. In the United States, such a&nbsp;case would not have made it to court (or would not last long if a&nbsp;complaint had been filed). But in the EU, the best one can say is that the publication&nbsp;<em>probably</em>&nbsp;would win.</p> <p>But not always. In October 2008 the European Court of Human Rights dismissed a&nbsp;complaint by French cartoonist Denis Leroy who had been convicted and fined for publishing a&nbsp;political cartoon condoning the World Trade Center attack in the days after 9/11. The cartoon, published in a&nbsp;Basque weekly newspaper, depicted the attack on the twin towers with a&nbsp;caption that was a&nbsp;play on a&nbsp;famous advertising slogan: “We all dreamt of it … Hamas did it.” The court held that the conviction did not violate Article 10 because the cartoonist’s expression of moral support for the terrorists “diminished the dignity of the victims.”&nbsp;<a href="#cite-130">130</a>&nbsp;Of course, the same calculus could be used to condemn&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>&nbsp;or&nbsp;<em>Jyllands‐​Posten</em>&nbsp;depending on how sentiment is running at any particular time. Anything is possible.</p> <p>This should serve as a&nbsp;cautionary note for those eager to impose punishment on whatever speech they detest. Anjem Choudary, whose&nbsp;<em>USA Today</em>&nbsp;op‐​ed in the aftermath of the&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>&nbsp;murders proclaimed that “Muslims do not believe in the concept of freedom of expression,” may have reason to reconsider his position. In August 2015 Choudary was arrested and charged with fomenting terrorism. To add to the irony, he was arrested along with Mohammad Mizanur Rahman, an associate who had served two years in prison for his part in a&nbsp;2006 protest over the&nbsp;<em>Jyllands‐​Posten</em>cartoons.<a href="#cite-131">131</a>&nbsp;It will be fascinating to see if their defense includes appeals to freedom of speech, and, if so, how that is assessed in the EU’s balancing regime.</p> <h2><a name="sec-8" id="sec-8"></a><strong>Conclusion</strong></h2> <p>In the end, the key point is not whether legal protections for freedom of expression should be absolute.&nbsp;<em>Jyllands‐​Posten</em>&nbsp;editor Flemming Rose wrote that the issue boils down to whether a&nbsp;free society chooses to defend the right to offend, or opts instead to champion a&nbsp;right not to be offended.<em>That</em>&nbsp;is the question. And, we have learned from hard experience in the United States that free expression cannot long survive without protecting outrageous and offensive speech.</p> <p>The Supreme Court has established the principle that citizens “must tolerate insulting, even outrageous, speech in order to provide adequate breathing space to the freedoms protected by the First Amendment.”<a href="#cite-132">132</a>&nbsp;“Boos v. Barry,485 U.S. 312 (1985)” Strong constitutional protections simply are not needed to protect speech with which everyone agrees or that is sufficiently nice. As a&nbsp;consequence, “the point of all speech protection … is to shield just those choices of content that in someone’s eyes are misguided, even hurtful.”<a href="#cite-133">133</a>&nbsp;The right to provoke, offend, and shock “lies at the core of the First Amendment.” This is because “[w]ithout the right to stand against society’s most strongly held convictions, the marketplace of ideas would decline into a&nbsp;boutique of the banal, as the urge to censor is greatest where debate is most disquieting and orthodoxy most entrenched.”<a href="#cite-134">134</a></p> <p>It is not easy to live up to such principles when expression is deeply disturbing and the speaker particularly provocative or outrageous. Yet our First Amendment jurisprudence recognizes that these protections will not long endure if we abandon them simply because the speech is outrageous or seemingly worthless. Nazis marching in Skokie and the lunatic rantings of the Westboro Baptist Church may seem to contribute little to public discourse, but they remind us that the purpose of some participants in the marketplace of ideas is to serve as bad examples. Thus, in our system, “judges defending the Constitution ‘must sometimes share [their] foxhole with scoundrels of every sort, but to abandon the post because of the poor company is to sell freedom cheaply. It is a&nbsp;fair summary of history to say that the safeguards of liberty have often been forged in controversies involving not very nice people.’”<a href="#cite-135">135</a></p> <p>From such difficult cases emerge constitutional protections that can weather the tests of time and turmoil. Higher values could not otherwise be preserved, for “[i]f there is any fixed star in our constitutional constellation, it is that no official, high or petty, can prescribe what shall be orthodox in politics, nationalism, religion, or other matters of opinion.”<a href="#cite-136">136</a>&nbsp;And that includes enforced civility. “West Virginia Board of Educ. v. Barnette, 319 U.S. 624 (1943)”</p> <h2>Notes</h2> <p id="cite-1">1. Dan Bilefsky and Maia de la Baume, “Terrorists Strike Paris Newspaper, Leaving 12 Dead,”&nbsp;<em>New York Times</em>, January 7, 2015.</p> <p id="cite-2">2. See generally, Flemming Rose,&nbsp;<em>The Tyranny of Silence</em>&nbsp;(Washington: Cato Institute, 2014); Rick Gladstone, “A Timeline of Threats and Acts of Violence over Blasphemy and Insults to Islam,”&nbsp;<em>New York Times</em>, January 8, 2015 p. A6.</p> <p id="cite-3">3. See, for example, James Taranto, “The Assassin’s Veto,”&nbsp;<em>Wall Street Journal</em>, January 23, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.wsj.com/articles/the-assassins-veto-1422046668" target="_blank">http://www.wsj.com/articles/the-assassins-veto-1422046668</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-4">4. . Timothy Garton Ash, “Defying the Assassin’s Veto,”&nbsp;<em>New York Review of Books</em>, February 19, 2015, p. 4</p> <p id="cite-5">5. Anthony Faiola and Griff Witte, “Tributes, Marches Held in France after Terror Attacks,”&nbsp;<em>Washington Post</em>, January 11, 2015, p. A1.</p> <p id="cite-6">6. Ian Black, “Hebdo Killings Condemned by Arab States—but Hailed Online by Extremists,”&nbsp;<em>Guardian</em>&nbsp;(London), January 7, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="http://theguardian.com/world/2015/jan/07/charlie-hebdo-killings-arab-states-jihadi-extremist-sympathizers-isis&#039;Charlie" target="_blank">http://theguardian.com/world/2015/jan/07/charlie-hebdo-killings-arab-states-jihadi-extremist-sympathizers-isis’Charlie</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-7">7. Council on American‐​Islamic Relations, “U.S. Muslims Condemn Paris Terror Attack, Defend Free Speech,” March 11, 2015,&nbsp;<code class="uri"><a href="http://cair.com/press-center/press-releases/12797-american-muslims-condemn-paris-terror-attack-defend-free-speech.html" target="_top">http://cair.com/press-center/press-releases/12797-american-muslims-condemn-paris-terror-attack-defend-free-speech.html</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-8">8. “Muslims in Philippines March against Charlie Hebdo,”&nbsp;<em>The Malaysian Insider</em>&nbsp;(Kuala Lumpur)<em>,</em> January 14, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="http://themalasianinsider.com/world/article/muslims-in-philippines-march-against-charlie-hebdo." target="_blank">http://themalasianinsider.com/world/article/muslims-in-philippines-march-against-charlie-hebdo</a>.</code></p> <p id="cite-9">9. Jack Linshi, “5,000 Rally Against Charlie Hebdo in Pakistan,”&nbsp;<em>Time</em>, January 18, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="http://time.com/3672871/charlie-hebdo-pakistan/" target="_blank">http://time.com/3672871/charlie-hebdo-pakistan/</a></code>; “Chechens Protest Against Charlie Hebdo Cartoons,”&nbsp;<em>Guardian</em>&nbsp;(London), January 19, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.theguardian.com/world /2015/jan/19/chechens-protest-charlie-hebdo-cartoons-grozny." target="_blank">http://www.theguardian.com/world /2015/jan/19/chechens-protest-charlie-hebdo-cartoons-grozny</a>.</code></p> <p id="cite-10">10. Anjem Choudary, “Why did France Allow the Tabloid to Provoke Muslims?”&nbsp;<em>USA</em><em>&nbsp;Today</em>, January 8, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="http://usatoday.com/story/opinion/2015/01/07/islam-allah-muslims-shariah-anjem-choudary-editorials-debates/21417461/." target="_blank"><code class="uri">http://usatoday.com/story/opinion/2015/01/07/islam-allah-muslims-shariah-anjem-choudary-editorials-debates/21417461/</code></a>.</code></p> <p id="cite-11">11. “Paris Terror at Charlie Hebdo Newspaper: Aussies Justify Attack,”&nbsp;<em>Herald‐​Sun</em>&nbsp;(Melborne), January 8, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.heraldsun.com.au/news/paris-terror-at-charlie-hebdo-newspaper-aussies-justify-attack/story-fni0fiyv-122717800371" target="_blank">http://www.heraldsun.com.au/news/paris-terror-at-charlie-hebdo-newspaper-aussies-justify-attack/story-fni0fiyv-122717800371</a>.</code></p> <p id="cite-12">12. Eric W. Dolan, “Catholic League Chief: Charlie Hebdo Editor Got Himself Murdered by Being a&nbsp;Narcissist,”&nbsp;<em>The Raw Story</em>, January 7, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.rawstory.com/rs/2015/01/catholic-league-chief-charlie-hebdo-editor-got-himself-murdered-by-being-a-narcissist/" target="_blank">http://www.rawstory.com/rs/2015/01/catholic-league-chief-charlie-hebdo-editor-got-himself-murdered-by-being-a-narcissist/</a>.</code></p> <p id="cite-13">13. Elizabeth Dias, “Pope Francis Speaks Out on Charlie Hebdo: ‘One Cannot Make Fun of Faith’,”&nbsp;<em>Time</em>, January 15, 2015.</p> <p id="cite-14">14. DeWayne Wickham, “Charlie Hebdo Crosses the Line,”&nbsp;<em>USA Today</em>, January 8, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.usatoday.com/story/opinion/2015/01/19/charlie-hebdo-cross-line-free-speech-covers-islam-limits-wickham/21960957/" target="_blank">http://www.usatoday.com/story/opinion/2015/01/19/charlie-hebdo-cross-line-free-speech-covers-islam-limits-wickham/21960957/</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-15">15. Lori Hinnant, “In Crackdown on Hate Speech, France Arrests 54 for Defending Terror,”&nbsp;<em>Associated Press</em>, January 14, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="https://www.bostonglobe.com/news/world/2015 /01/14/crackdown-hate-speech-france-arrests-for-defending-terror/exzmOcyRHLEPPWKJIV cHYK/story.html" target="_blank">https://www.bostonglobe.com/news/world/2015 /01/14/crackdown-hate-speech-france-arrests-for-defending-terror/exzmOcyRHLEPPWKJIV cHYK/story.html</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-16">16. Ibid. See also, Alexander Trowbridge, “French Arrests Draw Charges of Free Speech Hypocrisy,”&nbsp;<em>CBS News</em>, January 15, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.cbsnews.com/news/french-arrests-draw-charges-of-free-speech-hypocrisy/" target="_blank">http://www.cbsnews.com/news/french-arrests-draw-charges-of-free-speech-hypocrisy/</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-17">17. “French Comedian Dieudonné Faces Inquiry Over ‘Charlie Coulibaly’ Remark,”&nbsp;<em>Guardian</em>&nbsp;(London), January, 12, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.theguardian.com/world/2015/jan/12/french-comedian-dieudonne-charlie-coulibaly-prosecutor" target="_blank">http://www.theguardian.com/world/2015/jan/12/french-comedian-dieudonne-charlie-coulibaly-prosecutor</a></code>; Aurélien Breeden, “Dieudonné M’bala M’bala, French Comedian, Convicted of Condoning Terrorism,”&nbsp;<em>New York Times</em>, March 19, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.nytimes.com/2015/03/19/world/europe/dieudonne-mbala-mbala-french-comedian-convicted-of-condoning-terrorism.html" target="_blank">http://www.nytimes.com/2015/03/19/world/europe/dieudonne-mbala-mbala-french-comedian-convicted-of-condoning-terrorism.html</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-18">18. <em>New York Times v. Sullivan</em>, 376 U.S. 254, 269 (1964).</p> <p id="cite-19">19. <em>Terminiello v. City of Chicago</em>, 337 U.S. 1, 13 (1949), (Jackson, J., dissenting).</p> <p id="cite-20">20. Id., p. 4 (opinion for the Court by Douglas, J.).</p> <p id="cite-21">21. Id., p. 20–22 (Jackson, J., dissenting).</p> <p id="cite-22">22. Id., p. 28.</p> <p id="cite-23">23. Id., p. 32.</p> <p id="cite-24">24. Id.</p> <p id="cite-25">25. <em>Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire</em>, 315 U.S. 568 (1942).</p> <p id="cite-26">26. Id., p. 572.</p> <p id="cite-27">27. Id., p. 547. See James L. Swanson, “Unholy Fire: Cross Burning, Symbolic Speech, and the First Amendment in&nbsp;<em>Virginia v. Black</em>,”&nbsp;<em>Cato Supreme Court Review</em>&nbsp;<em>2002</em><em>–</em><em>2003</em>&nbsp;(Washington: Cato Institute, 2003), pp. 81, 90. “<em>Chaplinsky</em>&nbsp;has certainly been marginalized and might be viewed today as an ill‐​advised endorsement of the ‘heckler’s veto’.”</p> <p id="cite-28">28. <em>United States v. Stevens</em>, 559 U.S. 460, 469–471 (2010).</p> <p id="cite-29">29. <em>Brandenburg v. Ohio</em>, 395 U.S. 444, 447–449 (1969).</p> <p id="cite-30">30. <em>RAV v. City of St. Paul</em>, 505 U.S. 377, 380, 391 (1992).</p> <p id="cite-31">31. Id., pp. 393–394.</p> <p id="cite-32">32. <em>Black v. Virginia</em>, 538 U.S. 343 (2003).</p> <p id="cite-33">33. Sullivan, 376 U.S. p. 271, quoting NAACP v. Button, 371 U.S. 415, 445 (1963).</p> <p id="cite-34">34. <em>United States v. Playboy Entertainment Group</em>, Inc., 529 U.S. 803, 826 (2000).</p> <p id="cite-35">35. Id. at 818.</p> <p id="cite-36">36. <em>Hurley v. Irish‐​American Gay</em>, Lesbian and Bisexual Group of Boston, 515 U.S. 557, 574 (1995).</p> <p id="cite-37">37. Village of Skokie v. National Socialist Party of America, 69 Ill. 2d 605, 610 (1978). See National Socialist Party of Am. v. Village of Skokie, 432 U.S. 43 (1977).</p> <p id="cite-38">38. Village of Skokie, 69 Ill. 2d p. 618, (citation omitted).</p> <p id="cite-39">39. Compare Terminiello, 337 U.S. at 4, with Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U.S. 296 (1940).</p> <p id="cite-40">40. Compare <em>NAACP v. Claiborne Hardware Co.</em>, 458 U.S. 886 (1982), with Forsyth County v. Nationalist Movement, 505 U.S. 123, 134–135 (1992).</p> <p id="cite-41">41. Compare <em>McCullen v. Coakley</em>, 134&nbsp;S. Ct. 2518 (2014), with <em>Bigelow v. Virginia</em>, 421 U.S. 809 (1975).</p> <p id="cite-42">42. Compare RAV, 505 U.S. p. 382, with Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. 397, 408–410 (1989).</p> <p id="cite-43">43. <em>Hustler Magazine v. Falwell</em>, 485 U.S. 46, 56 (1988).</p> <p id="cite-44">44. <em>Snyder v. Phelps</em>, 562 U.S. 443, 460–461 (2011).</p> <p id="cite-45">45. Id., p. 448.</p> <p id="cite-46">46. Id., p. 449.</p> <p id="cite-47">47. Id., p. 453–455.</p> <p id="cite-48">48. Id., p. 458 (quoting Boos v. Barry, 485 U.S. 312, 322 (1988)).</p> <p id="cite-49">49. European Court of Human Rights, “Article 10,”&nbsp;<em>European Convention on Human Rights</em>&nbsp;(Strasbourg, FR: ECtHR, 2010), pp. 11, 13–14,&nbsp;<code class="uri"><a href="http://www.echr.coe.int/Documents/Convention_ENG.pdf" target="_blank">http://www.echr.coe.int/Documents/Convention_ENG.pdf</a>.</code></p> <p id="cite-50">50. Council of Europe, “Details of Treaty No. 198: Additional Protocol to the Convention on Cybercrime, Concerning the Criminalisation of Acts of a&nbsp;Racist and Xenophobic Nature Committed through Computer Systems,” <a href="http://conventions.coe.int/Treaty/en/Treaties/Html/198.htm">http://​con​ven​tions​.coe​.int/​T​r​e​a​t​y​/​e​n​/​T​r​e​a​t​i​e​s​/​H​t​m​l​/​1​9​8.htm</a>. (Entered into force on January 3, 2006.) Other instruments of international law also recognize the importance of freedom of expression but simultaneously require signatories to punish expression of racial or religious discrimination or hatred. The International Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination (CERD) and the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR) praise free expression but require signatories to punish hate speech. Article 4(a) of the CERD requires signatories to prohibit “all dissemination of ideas based on racial superiority or hatred.” United Nations, “International Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination,” 1969, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.ohchr.org/EN/ProfessionalInterest/Pages/CERD.aspx" target="_blank">http://www.ohchr.org/EN/ProfessionalInterest/Pages/CERD.aspx</a></code>; Article 20 of the ICCPR requires that signatories prohibit “any advocacy of national, racial, or religious hatred that constitutes incitement to discrimination, hostility, or violence.” United Nations, “International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights,” 1976, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.ohchr.org/EN/ProfessionalInterest/Pages/CCPR.aspx" target="_blank">http://www.ohchr.org/EN/ProfessionalInterest/Pages/CCPR.aspx</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-51">51. Council of Europe, “Fact Sheet on Hate Speech,” August 2009, p. 2, <a href="https://wcd.coe.int/ViewDoc.jsp?id=1477721">https://​wcd​.coe​.int/​V​i​e​w​D​o​c​.​j​s​p​?​i​d​=​1​4​77721</a>.</p> <p id="cite-52">52. Seurot v. France, Application No.&nbsp;<code class="uri"><a href="http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng" target="_top">57383/00</a></code>&nbsp;European Court of Human Rights, 2004, <a href="http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng?i=001-45005">http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng?i=001–45005</a>. See, “Fact Sheet on Hate Speech European,” European Court of Human Rights, June 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.echr.coe.int/Documents/FS_Hate_speech_ENG.pdfp.2." target="_blank">http://www.echr.coe.int/Documents/FS_Hate_speech_ENG.pdfp.2</a>.</code></p> <p id="cite-53">53. See, for example, Pavel Ivanov v. Russia, Application No. 35222/04, European Court of Human Rights, 2007, <code class="uri"><a href="http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng?i=001-79619" target="_blank">http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng?i=001-79619</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-54">54. Glimmerveen and Hagenbeek v. the Netherlands, Application Nos. 8348/78 &amp;&nbsp;8406/78, European Court of Human Rights, 1979, <code class="uri"><a href="http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng?i=001-74187" target="_blank">http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng?i=001-74187</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-55">55. See, for example, Garaudy v. France, Application No. 65831/01, European Court of Human Rights, 2003,&nbsp;<code class="uri"><a href="http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng-press?i=003-788339-805233" target="_top">http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng-press?i=003-788339-805233</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-56">56. Norwood v. the United Kingdom, European Court of Human Rights, 2004. See Hate Speech Fact Sheet, p. 3, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.echr.coe.int/Documents/FS_Hate_speech_ENG.pdf" target="_blank">http://www.echr.coe.int/Documents/FS_Hate_speech_ENG.pdf</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-57">57. “European Convention on Human Rights,” Article 10, p. 11,&nbsp;<code class="uri"><a href="http://www.echr.coe.int/Documents/Convention_ENG.pdf" target="_top">http://www.echr.coe.int/Documents/Convention_ENG.pdf</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-58">58. “Framework Decision on Combating Certain Forms and Expressions of Racism and Xenophobia by Means of Criminal Law,” Council of Europe, No. 2008/913/JHA, November 28, 2008, <code class="uri"><a href="http://eur-lex.europa.eu/legal-content/EN/TXT/?uri=URISERV:l33178" target="_blank">http://eur-lex.europa.eu/legal-content/EN/TXT/?uri=URISERV:l33178</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-59">59. See European Commission Against Racism and Intolerance, “Legal Measures to Combat Racism and Intolerance in the Member States of the Council of Europe: France,” p. 20, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.coe.int/t/dghl/monitoring/ecri/legal_research/national_legal_measures /France/France_SR.pdf" target="_blank">http://www.coe.int/t/dghl/monitoring/ecri/legal_research/national_legal_measures /France/France_SR.pdf</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-60">60. See European Commission Against Racism and Intolerance, “Legal Measures to Combat Racism and Intolerance in the Member States of the Council of Europe: Denmark,” pp. 7–8, <a href="http://www.coe.int/t/dghl/monitoring/ecri/legal_research/national_legal_measures/">http://​www​.coe​.int/​t​/​d​g​h​l​/​m​o​n​i​t​o​r​i​n​g​/​e​c​r​i​/​l​e​g​a​l​_​r​e​s​e​a​r​c​h​/​n​a​t​i​o​n​a​l​_​legal…</a> Denmark/Denmark_SR.pdf.</p> <p id="cite-61">61. See European Commission Against Racism and Intolerance, “Legal Measures to Combat Racism and Intolerance in the Member States of the Council of Europe: Netherlands,” pp. 10–14, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.coe.int/t/dghl/monitoring/ecri/legal_research/national_legal_measures/Netherlands/Netherlands_SR.pd" target="_blank">http://www.coe.int/t/dghl/monitoring/ecri/legal_research/national_legal_measures/Netherlands/Netherlands_SR.pdf</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-62">62. See European Commission Against Racism and Intolerance, “Legal Measures to Combat Racism and Intolerance in the Member States of the Council of Europe: United Kingdom,” pp. 21–24, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.coe.int/t/dghl/monitoring/ecri/legal_research/national_legal_measures/ United_Kingdom/United_Kingdom_SR.pdf" target="_blank">http://www.coe.int/t/dghl/monitoring/ecri/legal_research/national_legal_measures/ United_Kingdom/United_Kingdom_SR.pdf</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-63">63. “COE Fact Sheet 4,” Council of Europe, July 31, 2009, p. 3, <a href="https://wcd.coe.int/ViewDoc.jsp?id=1477721">https://​wcd​.coe​.int/​V​i​e​w​D​o​c​.​j​s​p​?​i​d​=​1​4​77721</a>.</p> <p id="cite-64">64. Ibid., p. 1.</p> <p id="cite-65">65. Ibid., p. 2.</p> <p id="cite-66">66.&nbsp;Féret v. Belgium, Application No.&nbsp;<code class="uri"><a href="http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng" target="_top">15615/07</a></code>&nbsp;European Court of Human Rights, 2009, <a href="http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng-press?i=003-2800730-3069797">http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng-press?i=003–2800730-3069797</a>.</p> <p id="cite-67">67. Le Pen v. France, Application No.&nbsp;<code class="uri"><a href="http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng" target="_top">18788/09</a></code>, European Court of Human Rights, 2010,&nbsp;<code class="uri"><a href="http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng-press?i=003-3117124-3455760" target="_top">http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng-press?i=003-3117124-3455760</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-68">68. Chaplinsky, 315 U.S., 572.</p> <p id="cite-69">69. Stevens, 559 U.S. p. 472. See also U.S. v. Alvarez, 132&nbsp;S.&nbsp;Ct. 2537, 2543–47 (2012); Brown v. EMA, 131&nbsp;S.&nbsp;Ct. 2729, 2734–35 (2011).</p> <p id="cite-70">70. See “European Convention on Human Rights,” European Court of Human Rights, Article 10, p. 11 and Article 17, p. 13.</p> <p id="cite-71">71. Reed v. Town of Gilbert, 135&nbsp;S. Ct. 2218, 2226–27 (2015); Playboy Entertainment Group, Inc., 529 U.S. p. 813.</p> <p id="cite-72">72. Burson v. Freeman, 504 U.S. 191, 211 (1993); Holder v. Humanitarian Law Project, 561 U.S. 1, 25–39 (2010). See Williams‐​Yulee v. The Florida Bar, 135&nbsp;S. Ct. 1636, 1668–70 (2015) (plurality op.).</p> <p id="cite-73">73. Miller v. California, 413 U.S. 15, 24 (1973).</p> <p id="cite-74">74. Stevens, 559 U.S. pp. 479–80, (emphasis in original).</p> <p id="cite-75">75. “COE Fact Sheet,” p. 3.</p> <p id="cite-76">76. Sullivan, 376 U.S. pp. 271–72.</p> <p id="cite-77">77. Federal Election Commission v. Wisconsin Citizens for Life, Inc., 551 U.S. 449, 474 (2007).</p> <p id="cite-78">78. “COE Fact Sheet,” p. 3.</p> <p id="cite-79">79. Ibid., pp. 3–4.</p> <p id="cite-80">80. Ibid., p. 2.</p> <p id="cite-81">81. 47 U.S.C. § 230 (c)(1).</p> <p id="cite-82">82. Zeran v. AOL, Inc., 129&nbsp;F.3d 327, 330 (4th Cir. 1997).</p> <p id="cite-83">83. Delfi AS v. Estonia, Application No. 64569/09, Grand Chamber, European Court of Human Rights, 2015.</p> <p id="cite-84">84. Magyar Tartalomszolgáltatók Egyesülete and Index​.hu Zrt v. Hungary, Application No. 22947/13, European Court of Human Rights, 2016.</p> <p id="cite-85">85. Melissa Locker, “Gunman Dead after Attack on a&nbsp;Free Speech Event and Synagogue in Copenhagen,”&nbsp;<em>Vanity Fair</em>, February 15, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.vanityfair.com/news/2015/02/gunman-dead-copenhagen-attacks" target="_blank">http://www.vanityfair.com/news/2015/02/gunman-dead-copenhagen-attacks</a></code>; Susanne Gargiulo, “Copenhagen Attacks: Police Kill Man During Shootout,”<em>CNN</em>, February 14, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.cnn.com/2015/02/14/europe/denmark-shooting/index.html" target="_blank">http://www.cnn.com/2015/02/14/europe/denmark-shooting/index.html</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-86">86. Liam Stack, “Texas Police Kill Gunmen at Exhibit Featuring Cartoons of Prophet Mohammed,”&nbsp;<em>New York Times</em>, May 3, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.nytimes.com/2015/05/04/us/gunmen-killed-after-firing-on-anti-islam-groups-event.html" target="_blank">http://www.nytimes.com/2015/05/04/us/gunmen-killed-after-firing-on-anti-islam-groups-event.html</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-87">87. For background on Geller, see Anne Barnard and Alan Feuer, “Outraged, and Outrageous,”&nbsp;<em>New York Times</em>, October 10, 2010, <code class="uri"><a href="http://query.nytimes.com/gst/fullpage.html?res=9E05EEDB113CF933A25753C1A9669D8B63&amp;pagewanted=all" target="_blank">http://query.nytimes.com/gst/fullpage.html?res=9E05EEDB113CF933A25753C1A9669D8B63&amp;pagewanted=all</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-88">88. Greg Richter, “Bill O’Reilly: Jesus Wouldn’t Have Sponsored ‘Draw Muhammad’ Event,”&nbsp;<em>Newsmax</em>, May 7, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.newsmax.com/Newsfront/Bill-OReilly-Jesus-draw-muhammad-ISIS/2015/05/07/id/643339/" target="_blank">http://www.newsmax.com/Newsfront/Bill-OReilly-Jesus-draw-muhammad-ISIS/2015/05/07/id/643339/</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-89">89. Greg Richter, “Peter King: Pamela Geller Put Lives at Risk ‘for No Good Reason’,”&nbsp;<em>Newsmax</em>, May 7, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.newsmax.com/US/Peter-King-pamela-geller-Muhammad-texas/2015/05/07/id/643303/" target="_blank">http://www.newsmax.com/US/Peter-King-pamela-geller-Muhammad-texas/2015/05/07/id/643303/</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-90">90. Hans Bader, “The ‘Draw Muhammad’ Contest and the Futility of Trying to Correct Journalistic Mistakes about the Law,” Competitive Enterprise Institute (blog), May 6, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="https://cei.org/blog/draw-muhammad-contest-and-futility-trying-correct-journalistic-mistakes-about-law" target="_blank"> https://cei.org/blog/draw-muhammad-contest-and-futility-trying-correct-journalistic-mistakes-about-law</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-91">91. Garry Trudeau, “The Abuse of Satire,”&nbsp;<em>The Atlantic</em>, April 2015,&nbsp;<code class="uri"><a href="http://www.theatlantic.com/international/archive/2015/04/the-abuse-of-satire/390312/" target="_top">http://www.theatlantic.com/international/archive/2015/04/the-abuse-of-satire/390312/</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-92">92. Pen American Center, “Rejecting the Assassin’s Veto,”&nbsp;<em>PEN America</em>&nbsp;(blog), April 26, 2015, <a href="http://www.pen.org/blog/rejecting-assassins-veto">http://​www​.pen​.org/​b​l​o​g​/​r​e​j​e​c​t​i​n​g​-​a​s​s​a​s​s​i​n​s​-veto</a>; Jennifer Schuessler, “Six PEN Members Decline Gala after Award for Charlie Hebdo,”&nbsp;<em>New York Times</em>, April 26, 2015, <a href="http://www.nytimes.com/2015/04/27/nyregion/six-pen-members-decline-gala-after-award-for-charlie-hebdo.html">http://​www​.nytimes​.com/​2​0​1​5​/​0​4​/​2​7​/​n​y​r​e​g​i​o​n​/​s​i​x​-​p​e​n​-​m​e​m​b​e​r​s​-​d​e​c​l​i​n​e​-gala…</a>.</p> <p id="cite-93">93. See, for example, Jeremy Waldron,&nbsp;<em>The Harm</em> <em>i</em><em>n Hate Speech</em> (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2012); Steven H. Shiffrin, “The Dark Side of the First Amendment,”&nbsp;<em>UCLA Law Review</em>&nbsp;61, no. 1480 (2014); Stanley Fish,&nbsp;<em>There’s no Such Thing as Free Speech, and It’s a&nbsp;Good Thing Too</em>&nbsp;(New York: Oxford University Press, 1990).</p> <p id="cite-94">94. Walker v. Texas Div., Sons of Confederate Veterans, Inc., 135&nbsp;S.&nbsp;Ct. 2239 (2015).</p> <p id="cite-95">95. Richard Fausset and Alan Blinder, “Era Ends as South Carolina Lowers Confederate Flag,”&nbsp;<em>New York Times</em>, July 10, 2015, <a href="http://www.nytimes.com/2015/07/11/us/south-carolina-confederate-flag.html">http://​www​.nytimes​.com/​2​0​1​5​/​0​7​/​1​1​/​u​s​/​s​o​u​t​h​-​c​a​r​o​l​i​n​a​-​c​o​n​f​e​d​e​r​a​t​e​-​f​l​ag.ht…</a>.</p> <p id="cite-96">96. Alvarez, 132&nbsp;S.&nbsp;Ct. at 2551–52 (Breyer, J., concurring).</p> <p id="cite-97">97. Brown, 131&nbsp;S.&nbsp;Ct. at 2766 (Breyer, J., dissenting).</p> <p id="cite-98">98. Sorrell v. IMS Health Inc., 131&nbsp;S.&nbsp;Ct. 2653 (2012) (Breyer, J., dissenting).</p> <p id="cite-99">99. Phelps, 562 U.S. pp. 462–63 (Breyer, J., concurring).</p> <p id="cite-100">100. Freedom of Expression in Europe, “Human Rights Files, No. 18,” (Council of Europe Publishing, March 2007) p. 9.</p> <p id="cite-101">101. Stephen Breyer,&nbsp;<em>The</em><em>&nbsp;Court and the World</em>&nbsp;(New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 2015), p. 254.</p> <p id="cite-102">102. Ibid., p. 256.</p> <p id="cite-103">103. Ibid., p. 257.</p> <p id="cite-104">104. Ibid., pp. 259–60.</p> <p id="cite-105">105. See generally Harry Kalven, Jr., The Negro and the First Amendment (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1965), pp. 140–60, (discussing the heckler’s veto as a&nbsp;barrier to civil rights).</p> <p id="cite-106">106. Brown v. Louisiana, 383 U.S. 131, 133 n.1 (1966); see also Cox v. Louisiana, 379 U.S. 536, 550–551 (1965); Edwards v. South Carolina, 372 U.S. 229 (1963).</p> <p id="cite-107">107. See, for example, Forsyth Cnty. v. Nationalist Movement, 505 U.S. 123, 134 (1992).</p> <p id="cite-108">108. See, for example, Street v. New York, 394 U.S. 576, 592 (1969), (“the possible tendency of … words to provoke violent retaliation” cannot justify restricting such words).</p> <p id="cite-109">109. Johnson, 491 U.S. pp. 408–09.</p> <p id="cite-110">110. Bible Believers v. Wayne County, Michigan, 805&nbsp;F.3d 228, 236 (6th Cir. 2015) (en banc).</p> <p id="cite-111">111. Id., pp. 238, 244.</p> <p id="cite-112">112. Id., p. 251 (quoting Glasson v. City of Louisville, 518&nbsp;F.2d 899, 906 (6th Cir. 1975)).</p> <p id="cite-113">113. Id., pp. 252, 254–55.</p> <p id="cite-114">114. Id., p. 261.</p> <p id="cite-115">115. See Catholic University of America, “Austria’s Top Justice Official Explains Europe’s Approach to Hate Crimes and Hate Speech,” <a href="http://www.law.edu/2015-Spring/Austrias-Top-Justice-Official-Explains-Europes-Approach-to-Hate-Crimes-and-Hate-Speech.cfm">http://​www​.law​.edu/​2​0​1​5​-​S​p​r​i​n​g​/​A​u​s​t​r​i​a​s​-​T​o​p​-​J​u​s​t​i​c​e​-​O​f​f​i​c​i​a​l​-​E​x​p​l​a​ins-E…</a>; See also&nbsp;“Hate Speech Legislation in Austria and the European Union,” YouTube video, 59:01, posted by the Catholic University of America Law School, February 26, 2015, <a href="https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=gpl0-bJY0gA">https://​www​.youtube​.com/​w​a​t​c​h​?​v​=​g​p​l​0​-​b​JY0gA</a>. </p> <p id="cite-116">116. See Dominika Bychawska‐​Siniarska, “Polish Blasphemy Law Declared Constitutional,”&nbsp;<em>MLRC Media Law Letter</em>, November 25, 2015, pp. 30–31.</p> <p id="cite-117">117. Mike Harris, “Europe’s Rules on Freedom of Information and Hate Speech,”&nbsp;<em>Index</em>, January 6, 2014, <a href="https://www.indexoncensorship.org/2014/01/eus-commitment-freedom-expression-freedom-information-hate-speech/#footnote1">https://​www​.index​on​cen​sor​ship​.org/​2​0​1​4​/​0​1​/​e​u​s​-​c​o​m​m​i​t​m​e​n​t​-​f​r​e​e​d​o​m​-​e​xpres…</a>.</p> <p id="cite-118">118. I.A. v. Turkey, Application No. 42571/98, European Court of Human Rights, 2005. “Hate Speech Fact Sheet,” p. 10, <a href="http://www.echr.coe.int/Documents/FS_Hate_speech_ENG.pdf">http://​www​.echr​.coe​.int/​D​o​c​u​m​e​n​t​s​/​F​S​_​H​a​t​e​_​s​p​e​e​c​h​_​E​N​G.pdf</a>.</p> <p id="cite-119">119. Sanjeev Bhaskar, “What Did ‘Life of Brian’ Ever Do For Us?,”&nbsp;<em>Telegraph</em>&nbsp;(London), November 29, 2009, <a href="http://www.telegraph.co.uk/culture/film/6679546/What-did-Life-of-Brian-ever-do-for-us.html">http://​www​.tele​graph​.co​.uk/​c​u​l​t​u​r​e​/​f​i​l​m​/​6​6​7​9​5​4​6​/​W​h​a​t​-​d​i​d​-​L​i​f​e​-​o​f​-​B​rian-…</a>; see “Monty Python’s Life of Brian: Religious Satire and Blasphemy Accusations,”<em>Wikipedia</em>, <code class="uri"><a href="https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Monty_Python&#039;s_Life_of_Brian#Religious_satire_and_blasphemy_accusations" target="_blank">https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Monty_Python's_Life_of_Brian#Religious_satire_and_blasphemy_accusations</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-120">120. See “Russia Overrules European Court of Human Rights,”&nbsp;<em>EurAc​tiv​.com</em>, July 14, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.euractiv.com/sections/europes-east/russia-overrules-european-court-human-rights-316305" target="_blank">http://www.euractiv.com/sections/europes-east/russia-overrules-european-court-human-rights-316305</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-121">121. See Masha Lipman, “The Absurd and Outrageous Trial of Pussy Riot,”&nbsp;<em>New Yorker,</em>&nbsp;August 7, 2012, <a href="http://www.newyorker.com/news/news-desk/the-absurd-and-outrageous-trial-of-pussy-riot">www​.newyork​er​.com/​n​e​w​s​/​n​e​w​s​-​d​e​s​k​/​t​h​e​-​a​b​s​u​r​d​-​a​n​d​-​o​u​t​r​a​g​e​o​u​s​-​t​r​i​a​l​-​o​f-pus…</a>.</p> <p id="cite-122">122. Jeffrey Tayler, “What Pussy Riot’s ‘Punk Prayer’ Really Said,”&nbsp;<em>The Atlantic</em>, November 8, 2012, <a href="http://www.theatlantic.com/international/archive/2012/11/what-pussy-riots-punk-prayer-really-said">www​.the​at​lantic​.com/​i​n​t​e​r​n​a​t​i​o​n​a​l​/​a​r​c​h​i​v​e​/​2​0​1​2​/​1​1​/​w​h​a​t​-​p​u​s​s​y​-​r​i​o​t​s​-punk…</a>.</p> <p id="cite-123">123. See Sonny Bunch, “Subjecting Free Speech to the Assassin’s Veto,”&nbsp;<em>Washington Post</em>, May 5, 2015, <a href="http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/act-four/wp/2015/05/05/subjecting-free-speech-to-the-assassins-veto">www​.wash​ing​ton​post​.com/​n​e​w​s​/​a​c​t​-​f​o​u​r​/​w​p​/​2​0​1​5​/​0​5​/​0​5​/​s​u​b​j​e​c​t​i​n​g​-​f​r​e​e​-spee…</a>.</p> <p id="cite-124">124. See Rose,&nbsp;<em>supra</em>&nbsp;note 2, pp. 96–97.</p> <p id="cite-125">125. Id., p. 98.</p> <p id="cite-126">126. Id., p. 122–23.</p> <p id="cite-127">127. See Bunch,&nbsp;<em>supra</em>&nbsp;note 123 p. 120.</p> <p id="cite-128">128. See Rose,&nbsp;<em>supra</em>&nbsp;note 2, p. 124.</p> <p id="cite-129">129. See Gregory Viscusi, “French Magazine Is Cleared over Muhammad Cartoons (Update 2),”&nbsp;<em>Bloomberg​.com</em>, March 22, 2007, <code class="uri"><a href="http://www.bloomberg.com/apps/news? pid=newsarchive&amp;sid=aJaZYqtP9ZFY&amp;refer=europe" target="_blank">http://www.bloomberg.com/apps/news? pid=newsarchive&amp;sid=aJaZYqtP9ZFY&amp;refer=europe</a></code>; Jacob Sullum, “How France Legitimizes Violent Responses to Offensive Speech,”&nbsp;<em>Rea​son​.com</em>, January 8, 2015, <code class="uri"><a href="http://reason.com/blog/2015/01/08/how-france-lends-legitimacy-to-violence" target="_blank">http://reason.com/blog/2015/01/08/how-france-lends-legitimacy-to-violence</a></code>.</p> <p id="cite-130">130. <em>Leroy v. France</em>, Application No. 36109/03, European Court of Human Rights, 2008,&nbsp;<code class="uri"><a href="http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng-press?i=003-2501837-2699727" target="_blank">http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng-press?i=003-2501837-2699727</a></code>; Hate Speech Fact Sheet, supra, p. 6.</p> <p id="cite-131">131. Karla Adam, “Briton Arrested Over Online Lectures,”&nbsp;<em>Washington Post</em>, August 6, 2015.</p> <p id="cite-132">132. <em>Boos v. Barry</em>, 485 U.S. 312, 322 (1985).</p> <p id="cite-133">133. <em>Hurley v. Irish‐​American Gay</em>, Lesbian and Bisexual Group of Boston, 515 U.S. 557, 574 (1995).</p> <p id="cite-134">134. <em>Rodriguez v. Maricopa County Community College District<em>, 605&nbsp;F.3d 703, 708 (9th Cir. 2010).</em></em></p> <p id="cite-135">135. <em>Snyder v. Phelps</em>, 580&nbsp;F.3d 206, 226 (4th Cir. 2009) (citation omitted), aff’d, 562 U.S. 443, 460–61 (2011).</p> <p id="cite-136">136. <em>West Virginia Board of Educ. v. Barnette</em>, 319 U.S. 624, 642 (1943).</p> </div> Tue, 24 May 2016 00:00:00 -0400 Robert Corn-Revere https://www.cato.org/publications/policy-analysis/hate-speech-laws-ratifying-assassins-veto The Assassin’s Veto https://www.cato.org/multimedia/cato-video/assassins-veto Robert Corn-Revere <p>View the full event here: <a href="https://www.cato.org/events/assassins-veto">https://​www​.cato​.org/​e​v​e​n​t​s​/​a​s​s​a​s​s​i​n​s​-veto</a></p> <p>European nations have often restricted “extreme speech” while the United States has protected speech short of immediate incitement to violence. Yet Supreme Court Justice Stephen Breyer has urged his fellow jurists to learn from the laws of other nations. Should the United States sustain its broad protections for speech or find a&nbsp;better, more European balance between freedom and other values?</p> Thu, 25 Feb 2016 11:14:00 -0500 Robert Corn-Revere https://www.cato.org/multimedia/cato-video/assassins-veto The Assassin’s Veto https://www.cato.org/multimedia/events/assassins-veto Robert Corn-Revere, John Samples <p>On the morning of January 7, 2015, Cherif and Said Kouachi, two brothers deeply offended by satirical drawings of the Muslim prophet Mohammad published in the French weekly newspaper&nbsp;<em>Charlie Hebdo</em>, exacted their own punishment for perceived blasphemy. They forced their way into a&nbsp;staff meeting in the newspaper’s offices and massacred 12 people. The phenomenon of killing or threatening to kill those who insult you or your way of life has come to be known as the assassin’s veto. Where should the law come down on this? Should it defend free expression at all costs no matter how inflammatory or who is offended? Or should it permit the state’s coercive power to silence those who trade in insult or invective? This conflict poses a&nbsp;fundamental question: how much expression must a&nbsp;free society tolerate? European nations have often restricted “extreme speech” while the United States has protected speech short of immediate incitement to violence. Yet Supreme Court Justice Stephen Breyer has urged his fellow jurists to learn from the laws of other nations. Should the United States sustain its broad protections for speech or find a&nbsp;better, more European balance between freedom and other values?</p> Thu, 07 Jan 2016 12:56:00 -0500 Robert Corn-Revere, John Samples https://www.cato.org/multimedia/events/assassins-veto To Confront the Assassin’s Veto, or to Ratify It? https://www.cato.org/publications/working-paper/confront-assassins-veto-or-ratify-it Robert Corn-Revere <div class="lead mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <p>The morning of January 7, 2015, Cherif and Said Kouachi, two brothers deeply offended by satirical drawings of the Muslim prophet Mohammad published in the French weekly newspaper <em>Charlie Hebdo</em>, exacted their own punishment for perceived blasphemy. They forced their way into a&nbsp;staff meeting in the newspaper’s offices and massacred twelve people.</p> </div> , <div class="mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <p>This was yet another grim marker in the cross‐​cultural conflict illustrated by events such as the Ayatollah Khomeini’s 1989 fatwah against Salman Rushdie for writing <em>The Satanic Verses</em>, the 2004 murder of filmmaker Theo van Gogh on the streets of Amsterdam for perceived insults to Islam, and the violent reaction to the cartoons of Mohammad published in the Danish newspaper <em>Jyllands‐​Posten</em> in 2005. And this is just a&nbsp;partial list.</p> <p>The phenomenon of killing or threatening to kill those who insult you or your way of life has come to be known as the assassin’s veto.</p> <p>It is a&nbsp;darker and more sinister version of “the heckler’s veto,” which the law of free expression is designed in substantial part to prevent. As Professor Timothy Garton Ash described it, “[w]here the heckler’s veto says merely ‘I will shout you down,’ the assassin’s version is ‘dare to express that and we will kill you.’&nbsp;”</p> <p>But where should the law come down on this? Should it defend free expression at all costs no matter how inflammatory the language or who is offended? Or should it permit the state’s coercive power to silence those who trade in insult or invective?</p> </div> Tue, 05 Jan 2016 11:40:00 -0500 Robert Corn-Revere https://www.cato.org/publications/working-paper/confront-assassins-veto-or-ratify-it Walker v. Texas Division, Sons of Confederate Veterans https://www.cato.org/publications/legal-briefs/walker-v-texas-division-sons-confederate-veterans Ilya Shapiro, Trevor Burrus, Robert Corn-Revere <div class="lead mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <p>Between 1861 and 1865, Texas was in a&nbsp;state of rebellion, waging war against the United States under the flag of the Confederacy. Texas has never offered any indication that it’s ashamed of this history. Indeed, the state recognizes April as Confederate History Month and spends January 19 celebrating Confederate Heroes Day. Yet now Texas is before the Supreme Court, arguing that its citizens’ sensibilities must be spared the sight of the Confederate flag in one particular context. The case involves a&nbsp;state agency that knows well what it is to cause universal offense: the Department of Motor Vehicles. Texas’s DMV, like that of many states, runs a&nbsp;program that allows private organizations such as charities, universities, and businesses to design their own “specialty” license plates—not to be confused with “vanity” plates, where the vehicle owner chooses the letters/​numbers on her plate—which can then be purchased through the DMV. The current range of customized plates on offer in the Lone Star State include messages that are patriotic (“God Bless America”), fannish (“Dallas Cowboys”), socially conscious (“Be a&nbsp;Blood Donor”), commercial (“Dr. Pepper”), and completely immoral (“Young Lawyers”). These custom plates include a&nbsp;near‐​limitless variety of slogans, symbols, logos, and color patterns—something for everyone’s taste. Except the Sons of Confederate Veterans. Their design, which included a&nbsp;miniature depiction of the Confederate battle flag, was rejected by the DMV on the grounds that&nbsp;<em>some</em>&nbsp;members of the public would find it offensive. It’s certainly right about that—and the relevant statute authorizes the DMV to reject any design that “might be offensive to any member of the public”—but do we really want the government determining what’s “too offensive”? Texas argues that it can be as censorial as it wishes because it can’t be forced to promote speech that it disagrees with or finds offensive. Regardless of whether that’s true—Cato takes no position on the question of whether a&nbsp;specialty plate is a “quasi‐​public forum” or any other legalistic concept—it represents a&nbsp;remarkable and disturbing willingness to ban expression that’s fully protected by the First Amendment merely because it&nbsp;<em>may</em>&nbsp;offend. (This is not a&nbsp;case about obscenity, incitement, “true threat,” or one of the few other categories of unprotected speech.) Texas’s stance is particularly worrying given that it comes at a&nbsp;time when free speech is being threatened to an extent not seen in some time. Throughout Europe and the Anglosphere, liberal democracies are increasingly intolerant of offensive speech, enacting open‐​ended hate‐​speech laws, prohibitions on blasphemy, and “human rights” protections against insulting not just individuals but communities and abstract concepts. Domestically, Texas’s position mirrors that of many colleges and universities, whose coddling speech codes have rendered the idea of the campus as a&nbsp;place for vigorous and open academic discourse a&nbsp;laughable theory. So effective has this program of re‐​education been that. in a&nbsp;recent poll, nearly 40 percent of respondents believed that the First Amendment goes “too far” in protecting free speech—up from less than 20 percent just two years ago. Cato disagrees. Together with a&nbsp;team of expert offenders of good taste—and equally expert defenders of free speech—we have filed an&nbsp;<em>amicus</em>&nbsp;brief urging the Supreme Court to reaffirm that the First Amendment protects the speech of unpopular minorities, even when the proffered justification for censorship is its putative “offensiveness.” We argue that offensiveness is intrinsically valuable in the marketplace of ideas because it enables self‐​actualization and the freedom of association, among other important interests. Not only does the right to be offensive secure the livelihood of our favorite comedians, it protects scientific and medical researchers in their quest to push the limits of human knowledge into fields once considered taboo and enables one religion’s heretic to become another’s prophet. And should a&nbsp;member of a&nbsp;third faith, or no faith at all, wish to define himself as an iconoclast by mocking, degrading, or insulting that heretic cum prophet—be it Muhammed, L. Ron Hubbard, or Mark Steyn—that too, is protected by the First Amendment. There’s no “offensiveness” exception to the First Amendment and it would be insulting for the Supreme Court to allow Texas to tell us what’s offensive. Those who are offended shouldn’t have a&nbsp;veto over free expression and putative offenders should be judged in the court of public opinion.</p> </div> Tue, 17 Feb 2015 08:51:00 -0500 Ilya Shapiro, Trevor Burrus, Robert Corn-Revere https://www.cato.org/publications/legal-briefs/walker-v-texas-division-sons-confederate-veterans Minority Television Project v. FCC https://www.cato.org/publications/legal-briefs/minority-television-project-v-fcc Robert Corn-Revere, Ronald G. London, Lisa B. Zycherman, Ilya Shapiro, Trevor Burrus <div class="lead mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <p>Remember broadcast television? Amid the avalanche of new streaming services, DVRs, and Rokus, not to mention cable TV, some people may have forgotten—or, if they’re under 25, never known—that there are TV shows in the air that can be captured with an antenna. The Supreme Court certainly hasn’t forgotten, given that it maintains an outdated rule that broadcast TV gets less First Amendment protection than cable, video‐​on‐​demand, or almost anything else, a&nbsp;rule dating to the 1969 case of <em>Red Lion Broadcasting Co. v. FCC</em>. That lower standard of protection comes from the belief that the broadcast‐​frequency spectrum is scarce, and thus that the Federal Communications Commission is properly charged with licensing the spectrum for the public “interest, convenience, and necessity.” But if newspapers or magazines were similarly licensed, the First Amendment violation would be obvious to all but the most hardened censor. Hence this case: Minority Television Project is an independent, noncommercial license‐​holding TV station in San Francisco. Unlike most noncommercial license holders, Minority TV receives no PBS money. Because it’s an over‐​the‐​air broadcaster, however, it must comply with the restrictions placed on the licenses by Congress and the FCC, including prohibitions on paid commercials and political ads. Minority TV challenged these restrictions as violating the First Amendment. Applying <em>Red Lion</em> lower First Amendment standard, the district court, a&nbsp;panel of the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit, and even the <em>en banc</em> Ninth Circuit (11 judges rather than the usual 3) all ruled against Minority TV. On petition for certiorari to the Supreme Court, Minority TV argues that <em>Red Lion</em>’s rationale for reducing broadcasters’ rights is outdated and should be overruled. Cato has filed an amicus brief in support of Minority TV, agreeing that it’s time to give broadcast TV full First Amendment protection. Just as we argued in 2011’s <em><a href="https://www.cato.org/publications/legal-briefs/fcc-v-fox-television-stations" target="_blank">FCC v. Fox Television Stations</a></em>—where the Court chose to evade the question—it’s time to update our law to fit current realities. The way that people consume information and entertainment has changed dramatically since 1969. Rather than three broadcast networks, we have hundreds of channels of various kinds, and increasingly people are forgoing traditional TV altogether. The FCC can still license broadcasters—that system isn’t going away anytime soon regardless of the next mind‐​boggling innovation—but the conditions it places on those licenses have to satisfy strict First Amendment scrutiny, especially when they pertain to political speech. The Supreme Court should take this case in order to update its treatment of broadcasters’ speech rights, including a&nbsp;requirement that the government offer a&nbsp;truly compelling justification any time it wants to restrict them.</p> </div> Fri, 18 Apr 2014 12:55:00 -0400 Robert Corn-Revere, Ronald G. London, Lisa B. Zycherman, Ilya Shapiro, Trevor Burrus https://www.cato.org/publications/legal-briefs/minority-television-project-v-fcc Robert Corn‐​Revere discusses his paper “Fairness 2.0: Media Content Regulation in the 21st Century on WLW’s Mike McConnell Show https://www.cato.org/multimedia/radio-highlights/robert-cornrevere-discusses-paper-fairness-20-media-content-regulation-21st-century-wlws-mike-mcconnell-show Sun, 22 Nov 2009 19:00:00 -0500 Robert Corn-Revere https://www.cato.org/multimedia/radio-highlights/robert-cornrevere-discusses-paper-fairness-20-media-content-regulation-21st-century-wlws-mike-mcconnell-show Fairness 2.0: Media Content Regulation in the 21st Century https://www.cato.org/publications/policy-analysis/fairness-20-media-content-regulation-21st-century Robert Corn-Revere <div class="lead mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <p>Civil libertarians feared that a&nbsp;change of administrations would herald a&nbsp;revived Fairness Doctrine, a&nbsp;policy that previously permitted the government to oversee broadcast news coverage for “balanced views.” A&nbsp;return to the Fairness Doctrine, however, now seems unlikely. It is very likely, however, that politicians from both the left and the right will try to extend government control over the media beyond current policies. New rules adopted or proposed by the Federal Communications Commission suggest that the agency may be poised to enforce the most intensive government oversight of broadcast programming in decades—perhaps even in the history of the agency. The FCC voted last year to require each broadcast licensee to file quarterly “enhanced disclosure” reports—highly detailed information regarding its programming and editorial choices. This information will be used by organized groups to file complaints to pressure broadcasters to air programming that the complainants prefer. The FCC is also formulating programming guidelines based on the enhanced disclosure reports purporting to ensure that broadcasters meet local needs. This “broadcast localism” effort may also require broadcasters to appoint local boards to oversee their performance and their editorial decisions. As the FCC seeks to expand regulation of broadcast media, the traditional justification for its authority—spectrum scarcity—has lost credibility, and the agency’s new efforts are likely to run afoul of the First Amendment.</p> </div> Tue, 10 Nov 2009 00:00:00 -0500 Robert Corn-Revere https://www.cato.org/publications/policy-analysis/fairness-20-media-content-regulation-21st-century FCC v. Fox Television Stations, Inc.: Awaiting the Next Act https://www.cato.org/supreme-court-review/2008-2009/fcc-v-fox-television-stations-inc-awaiting-next-act Tue, 01 Sep 2009 00:00:00 -0400 Robert Corn-Revere https://www.cato.org/supreme-court-review/2008-2009/fcc-v-fox-television-stations-inc-awaiting-next-act Narrow Issue of Taxpayer Standing Highlights Wide Divisions Among the Justices https://www.cato.org/supreme-court-review/2006-2007/narrow-issue-taxpayer-standing-highlights-wide-divisions-among Sat, 01 Sep 2007 00:00:00 -0400 Robert Corn-Revere https://www.cato.org/supreme-court-review/2006-2007/narrow-issue-taxpayer-standing-highlights-wide-divisions-among Ashcroft v. ACLU II: The Beat Goes On https://www.cato.org/supreme-court-review/2003-2004/ashcroft-v-aclu-ii-beat-goes Wed, 01 Sep 2004 00:00:00 -0400 Robert Corn-Revere https://www.cato.org/supreme-court-review/2003-2004/ashcroft-v-aclu-ii-beat-goes United States v. American Library Association: A Missed Opportunity for the Supreme Court to Clarify Application of First Amendment Law to Publicly Funded Expressive Institutions https://www.cato.org/supreme-court-review/2002-2003/united-states-v-american-library-association-missed-opportunity Mon, 01 Sep 2003 00:00:00 -0400 Robert Corn-Revere https://www.cato.org/supreme-court-review/2002-2003/united-states-v-american-library-association-missed-opportunity Cyberspace Cases Force Court to Reexamine Basic Assumptions of Obscenity and Child Pornography Jurisprudence https://www.cato.org/supreme-court-review/2001-2002/cyberspace-cases-force-court-reexamine-basic-assumptions-obscenity Sun, 01 Sep 2002 00:00:00 -0400 Robert Corn-Revere https://www.cato.org/supreme-court-review/2001-2002/cyberspace-cases-force-court-reexamine-basic-assumptions-obscenity Caught in the Seamless Web: Does the Internet’s Global Reach Justify Less Freedom of Speech? https://www.cato.org/publications/briefing-paper/caught-seamless-web-does-internets-global-reach-justify-less-freedom-speech Robert Corn-Revere <div class="lead mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <p>A federal appellate court will decide this year whether French anti‐​discrimination law can restrict freedom of speech on U.S.-based websites that are accessible in France. A&nbsp;Paris court ruled in 2000 that the Yahoo! website violated French law because its users offered for sale certain Nazi artifacts. However, to force compliance with the order, French plaintiffs must seek enforcement from a&nbsp;U.S. court. In response, Yahoo! sought a&nbsp;declaratory ruling and a&nbsp;federal district court held that enforcing the French order would violate the First Amendment. The matter is now on appeal.</p> </div> , <div class="mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <p>The Yahoo! case presents the question of whether the Internet should be governed by myriad local censorship laws from around the world. U.S. courts have held uniformly that the Internet should receive the highest degree of First Amendment protection. They have been influenced profoundly by the medium’s global reach and have invalidated most restrictions so as not to interrupt the “never‐​ending worldwide conversation” that the Internet makes possible. A&nbsp;contrary result in the Yahoo! case would embrace a&nbsp;very different philosophy—that Internet speakers must “show their papers” at each nation’s borders to ensure that their speech is acceptable to local authorities.</p> <p>Other nations may treat their citizens as fragile children if they wish, or worse, as enemies of the state. But U.S. courts should not permit the seeds of foreign censorship to be planted on U.S. soil by finding that such restrictions are enforceable here.</p> </div> Wed, 24 Jul 2002 00:00:00 -0400 Robert Corn-Revere https://www.cato.org/publications/briefing-paper/caught-seamless-web-does-internets-global-reach-justify-less-freedom-speech Regulation in Newspeak: The FCC’s Children’s Television Rules https://www.cato.org/publications/policy-analysis/regulation-newspeak-fccs-childrens-television-rules Robert Corn-Revere <div class="lead mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <p>In August 1996 the Federal Communications Commission adopted rules requiring television broadcasters to air at least three hours per week of children’s “educational” programming. The FCC provided little justification for imposing that requirement. Studies suggested that most broadcasters were already airing at least three hours of programming per week that would qualify as educational. And the FCC’s order ignores the educational video programming for children that is available on media that compete with broadcasting, such as cable, satellite, and videocassettes. Finally, the theory behind the mandate is that the market will not provide educational programming on its own because the audience does not demand it–another way of saying that such programming cannot attract an audience. But that also means that mandates are not a&nbsp;solution, since the FCC cannot force anyone who would not already have done so to watch educational programming.</p> </div> , <div class="mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <p>All this suggests that the politics of the presidential campaign, where lip service to the idea of “family values” was a&nbsp;favored theme, had more to do with the adoption of the rules than did a&nbsp;real concern for children. And while the FCC represents its rules as mere “guidelines,” broadcasters who ignore the rules bear the ominous burden of proving, in a&nbsp;full hearing, that they have complied with the Children’s Television Act of 1990. The legislative history of the CTA clearly shows that such a&nbsp;programming mandate was not what Congress intended when it passed the act. The FCC’s rulemaking also violates broadcasters’ First Amendment rights, forcing them to transmit government‐​approved “educational” speech.</p> </div> , <blockquote class="blockquote"> <div> <p><em>Syllogisms à&nbsp;la Mode</em>–If you are against labor racketeers, then you are against the working man. If you are against demagogues, then you are against democracy. If you are against Christianity, then you are against God. If you are against trying a&nbsp;can of Old Dr. Quack’s Cancer Salve, then you are in favor of letting Uncle Julius die.</p> <p align="right"><em>– H. L. Mencken</em><a href="#FOOTNOTE_1"><sup>[1]</sup></a></p> <p>FCC chairman [Reed] Hundt has set out to wear down his colleagues’ opposition to his proposal [to require broadcast licensees to transmit three hours per week of children’s educational programming] in part by accusing them of waging a&nbsp;campaign against kids. </p> <p align="right"><em>Cleveland Plain Dealer</em><a href="#FOOTNOTE_2"><sup>[2]</sup></a></p> </div> </blockquote> <cite> </cite> , <div class="mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <p>On August 8, 1996, the Federal Communications Commission adopted new rules requiring television broadcasters to air more children’s educational programming. Less than three weeks later, the Food and Drug Administration announced that it would assert jurisdiction over cigarettes and adopted rules to sharply curtail tobacco advertising. Judging by the growing number of regulations of media content that are being justified by the perceived need to protect minors, it takes a&nbsp;child to raze the constitutional rights of a&nbsp;village. </p> <p>Despite the government’s characterization of its regulatory action as merely setting “guidelines” to assist broadcasters with compliance, it is clear that the FCC’s rules establish programming mandates that a&nbsp;licensee may ignore only at its peril. The lack of justification for the requirements and the twisted logic on which they are based suggest that the recent presidential campaign, in which “family values” were the Holy Grail, better explains the rules’ development than does a&nbsp;genuine concern for children or education. In addition, the three‐​hour programming requirement exceeds the FCC’s statutory mandate under the Children’s Television Act of 1990 and encroaches on broadcasters’ First Amendment rights. </p> </div> Wed, 19 Feb 1997 00:00:00 -0500 Robert Corn-Revere https://www.cato.org/publications/policy-analysis/regulation-newspeak-fccs-childrens-television-rules “V” Is Not for Voluntary https://www.cato.org/publications/briefing-paper/v-is-not-voluntary Robert Corn-Revere <div class="lead mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <p>Proponents of V‐​chip legislation tout it as a “voluntary” system that imply restores parental control of the family television. But there is nothing voluntary about the rating systems being proposed. First, ratings for television programs would be imposed either by a&nbsp;government commission or by the industry under a&nbsp;government‐​compelled deadline. Second, the courts have invalidated government‐​imposed ratings systems for movies as “unbridled censorship,” and the same First Amendment considerations would apply to television. Third, the legislation does not amount to “parental responsibility,” for parents would not be the ones to determine what is objectionable. Rather, parents would gain the ability only to tune out programs deemed by the government to be unfit for family viewing.</p> </div> , <div class="mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <p>Contrary to the characterizations of its congressional sponsors, the V- chip is not a&nbsp;voluntary solution to the issue of televised violence, nor is the focal point of the debate the V‐​chip itself. The heart of the debate is whether the Constitution permits the government to impose a&nbsp;ratings system for television programming. It does not.</p> </div> Thu, 03 Aug 1995 00:00:00 -0400 Robert Corn-Revere https://www.cato.org/publications/briefing-paper/v-is-not-voluntary New Age Comstockery: Exon vs. the Internet https://www.cato.org/publications/policy-analysis/new-age-comstockery-exon-vs-internet Robert Corn-Revere <div class="lead mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <p>On June 14 the Senate voted 84 to 16 to approve the Communications Decency Act of 1995, proposed by Sen. James Exon (D‐​Neb.). The bill proposes to outlaw the use of computers and telephone lines to transmit “indecent” material, a&nbsp;category of speech that the Supreme Court has held to be protected by the First Amendment. The measure would impose jail terms and fines on anyone who used a “telecommunications facility” to transmit any obscene information or image, or any indecent information or image to a&nbsp;person under the age of 18. If a&nbsp;similar provision is included in legislation being debated in the House of Representatives, and is signed into law by the president, it will usher in a&nbsp;new age of Comstockery in America.</p> </div> , <div class="mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default"> <p>The term “Comstockery,” coined by George Bernard Shaw, refers to overzealous moralizing like that of Anthony Comstock, whose Society for the Suppression of Vice censored literature in America for more than 60&nbsp;years. Under the so called Comstock laws, classic works by such authors as D. H. Lawrence, Theodore Dreiser, Edmund Wilson, and James Joyce were routinely suppressed. Other targets of the society’s crusades included such literary giants as Tolstoy and Balzac. The more recent law of indecency, which traces its heritage to Comstock, has been used to restrict some of the same literary works. The Exon bill would extend that repressive regime to the Internet and online services and thus threatens to undermine the promise of the emerging digital age.</p> </div> Wed, 28 Jun 1995 00:00:00 -0400 Robert Corn-Revere https://www.cato.org/publications/policy-analysis/new-age-comstockery-exon-vs-internet